Advertisement

Synthese

pp 1–20 | Cite as

Why mental content is not like water: reconsidering the reductive claims of teleosemantics

  • Peter Schulte
Article
  • 61 Downloads

Abstract

According to standard teleosemantics, intentional states are selectional states. This claim is put forward not as a conceptual analysis, but as a ‘theoretical reduction’—an a posteriori hypothesis analogous to ‘water = H2O’. Critics have tried to show that this meta-theoretical conception of teleosemantics leads to unacceptable consequences. In this paper, I argue that there is indeed a fundamental problem with the water/H2O analogy, as it is usually construed, and that teleosemanticists should therefore reject it. Fortunately, there exists a viable alternative to the water/H2O model which avoids the fundamental problem, while explaining the a posteriori character of teleosemantics equally well.

Keywords

Mental content Teleosemantics Naturalistic theories of content Reduction Reductive explanation 

Notes

Acknowledgements

This paper has greatly benefited from the constructive criticisms of five anonymous referees for this journal. For helpful feedback on (much) earlier versions of this paper, I would also like to thank Ansgar Beckermann, Frank Hofmann, Joachim Horvath, Fabian Hundertmark, Brian Leahy, Manolo Martínez, Bence Nanay, Christian Nimtz, David Papineau, Eva Schmidt and other participants of the ‘Minds without Magic’ workshop 2013 and the DGPhil conference 2014. This research was supported by the project ‘Advancing Teleosemantics’ (SCHU 2860/2-1, NI 1320/2-1), funded by the German Research Foundation (DFG).

References

  1. Antony, L. (1996). Equal rights for swamp-persons. Mind and Language, 11, 70–75.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Beckermann, A. (2009). What is property physicalism? In B. McLaughlin, A. Beckermann, & S. Walter (Eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Braddon-Mitchell, D., & Jackson, F. (1997). The teleological theory of content. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 75, 474–489.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Braddon-Mitchell, D., & Jackson, F. (2002). A phyrric victory for teleonomy. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 80, 372–377.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Broad, C. D. (1925). The Mind and its Place in Nature. London: Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
  6. Clapp, L. (2001). Disjunctive properties and multiple realizations. The Journal of Philosophy, 98, 111–136.Google Scholar
  7. Considine, G. D. (Ed.). (2005). Van Nostrand’s Encyclopedia of Chemistry. Hoboken, NJ: Wiley.Google Scholar
  8. Davidson, D. (1987). Knowing One’s Own Mind. Proceedings and addresses of the American philosophical association, 60, 441–458.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Dretske, F. (1988). Explaining behavior. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  10. Friedman, H. L. (1993). Water. In S. P. Parker (Ed.), McGraw-Hill encyclopedia of chemistry (2nd ed., pp. 1155–1157). New York: McGraw-Hill.Google Scholar
  11. Hendry, R. F. (2006). Elements, compounds, and other chemical kinds. Philosophy of Science, 73, 864–875.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Jackson, F. (1998). From metaphysics to ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  13. Lepore, E., & Loewer, B. (1989). Making mind matter more. Philosophical Topics, 18, 175–191.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Mill, J. S. (1843/1973). System of Logic, Ratiocinative and Inductive. In J. M. Robson (ed.): Collected works of John Stuart mill (Vols. 7–8), Toronto: University of Toronto Press.Google Scholar
  15. Millikan, R. (1984). Language, thought, and other biological categories. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  16. Millikan, R. (1989). In defense of proper functions. Philosophy of Science, 56, 288–302.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Millikan, R. (2000). On clear and confused ideas. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Millikan, R. (2004). Varieties of meaning. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  19. Millikan, R. (2010). On knowing the meaning; with a coda on Swampman. Mind, 119, 43–81.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Neander, K. (1991). The teleological notion of ‘function’. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 69, 454–468.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Neander, K. (1996). Swampman meets Swampcow. Mind and Language, 11, 118–129.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Neander, K. (2012). Teleological Theories of Mental Content. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Berlin: Springer.Google Scholar
  23. Neander, K. (2017). A mark of the mental. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  24. Papineau, D. (1993). Philosophical naturalism. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  25. Papineau, D. (1998). Teleosemantics and indeterminacy. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 76, 1–14.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Papineau, D. (2001). The status of teleosemantics, or how to stop worrying about Swampman. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 79, 279–289.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Papineau, D. (2009). The poverty of analysis. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Suppl., 83, 1–30.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Papineau, D. (2016). Teleosemantics. In D. L. Smith (Ed.), How biology shapes philosophy (pp. 95–120). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  29. Partington, J. R. (1962). A history of chemistry (Vol. III). London: Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Peters, Uwe. (2014). Teleosemantics, Swampman, and strong representationalism. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 90, 273–288.Google Scholar
  31. Sebastián, M. Á. (2017). Functions and mental representation: The theoretical role of representations and its real nature. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 16, 317–336.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Soames, S. (2002). Beyond rigidity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Walter, S. (2010). Taking realization seriously: no cure for epiphobia. Philosophical Studies, 151, 207–226.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V., part of Springer Nature 2018

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyBielefeld UniversityBielefeldGermany

Personalised recommendations