Advertisement

Synthese

pp 1–27 | Cite as

Ideology and its role in metaphysics

  • Peter FinocchiaroEmail author
Article

Abstract

Metaphysicians now typically distinguish between a theory’s ontology and its ideology. But besides a few cursory efforts, no one has explained the role of ideology in theory choice. In this paper I develop a framework for discussing how differing approaches to ideology impact metaphysical disputes. I first provide an initial characterization of ideology and develop two contrasting types of criteria used to evaluate its quality. In using externalist criteria, we judge the quality of a theory’s ideology by its relation to external features of the world. In contrast, in using internalist criteria, we judge the quality of a theory’s ideology by features internal to the theory and the theorizer, e.g. the intelligibility of the terminology employed. I then argue for an unrestricted application of externalist criteria, what I call maximal realism. According to maximal realism, we ought to apply externalist criteria to the entirety of a theory’s ideology—to not only predicates but also to quantifiers and logical operators. I defend maximal realism from what I take to be the best objection to it: that the view leads to bad questions. As part of my defense, I argue that those who would restrict their application of externalist criteria either adopt an unjustified partition of ideology or reject seemingly benign questions. Finally, I apply my discussion of ideology to two extant metaphysical disputes.

Keywords

Ideology Metametaphysics Methodology Ontological disagreement Theory choice 

Notes

Acknowledgements

I owe an enormous debt of gratitude to many people for their contributions to the development of this paper over the past few years. Among those people are: Sara Bernstein, Andrew Brenner, Anjan Chakravartty, Rebecca Chan, Justin Christy, Michael Longenecker, Daniel Nolan, David Pattillo, Callie K. Phillips, Benjamin Rossi, Margaret Schmitt, S.C. Schramm, Jeff Snapper, Jeff Speaks, Meghan Sullivan, Jeffrey Tolly, Jason Turner, Peter van Inwagen, and two anonymous reviewers for Synthese. I owe an even more enormous debt of gratitude to Michael Rea for the philosophical, practical, and emotional wisdom that he so generously shared throughout this paper’s journey.

References

  1. Bennett, K. (2009). Composition, colocation, and metaontology. In Chalmers et al. (2009), pp. 38–76.Google Scholar
  2. Bigelow, J. (1996). Presentism and properties. Philosophical Perspectives, 10, 35–52.Google Scholar
  3. Bricker, P. (2008). Concrete possible worlds. In T. Sider, J. Hawthorne, & D. W. Zimmerman (Eds.), Contemporary debates in metaphysics. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  4. Burgess, J., & Rosen, G. (1997). A subject with no object. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  5. Cameron, R. (2011). Truthmaking for presentists. Oxford Studies in Metaphysics, 6, 55–100.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Cameron, R. (2012). Why Lewis’s analysis of modality succeeds in its reductive ambitions. Philosophers’ Imprint 12.Google Scholar
  7. Carnap, R. (1950). Empiricism, semantics and ontology. Revue Internationale de Philosophie, 4, 20–40.Google Scholar
  8. Chalmers, D., Manley, D., & Wasserman, R. (Eds.). (2009). Metametaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  9. Cowling, S. (2013). Ideological parsimony. Synthese, 190, 3889–3908.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Crisp, T. (2007). Presentism and the grounding objection. Noûs, 41, 90–109.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Dasgupta, S. (2009). Individuals: An essay in revisionary metaphysics. Philosophical Studies, 145, 35–67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Decock, L. (2002). Trading ontology for ideology. The interplay of logic, set theory and semantics in Quine’s philosophy. Synthese Library. Kluwer/Springer.Google Scholar
  13. Decock, L. (2004). Quine’s ideological debacle. Principia, 8, 85–102.Google Scholar
  14. Field, H. (1980). Science without numbers. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  15. Fine, K. (1994). Essence and modality. Philosophical Perspectives, 8, 1–16.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Finocchiaro, P. (Forthcoming a). The explosion of being: Ideological kinds in theory choice. Philosophical Quarterly, 1–28.Google Scholar
  17. Finocchiaro, P. (Forthcoming b). The intelligibility of metaphysical structure. Philosophical Studies, 1–26.Google Scholar
  18. Fisher, A. R. J. (2016). Truthmaking and fundamentality. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 97, 448–473.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Fisher, A. R. J. (2012). Ideology, truthmaking, and fundamentality. Ph.D. thesis, Syracuse University.Google Scholar
  20. Frost-Arnold, G. (2013). Carnap, Tarski, and Quine at Harvard. Open Court.Google Scholar
  21. Goodman, N. (1955). Fact, fiction, and forecast. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  22. Goodman, N., & Quine, W. V. (1947). Steps toward a constructive nominalism. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 12, 105–122.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Haslanger, S. (2000). Gender and race: (What) are they? (What) Do we want them to be? Noûs, 34, 31–55.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Hawthorne, J. (2009). Superficialism in ontology. In Chalmers et al. (2009), pp. 213–230.Google Scholar
  25. Hirsch, E. (2013). The metaphysically best language. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 87, 709–716.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Kierland, B., & Monton, B. (2007). Presentism and the objection from being-supervenience. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 85, 485–497.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Krämer, S. (2010). How not to defend ontological cheats. Analysis, 70, 290–296.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Lewis, D. (1983). New work for a theory of universals. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 61, 343–377.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Lewis, D. (1984). Putnam’s paradox. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 62, 221–236.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Lewis, D. (1986). On the plurality of worlds. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.Google Scholar
  31. McDaniel, K. (2009). Ways of being. In Chalmers et al. (2009), pp. 290–319.Google Scholar
  32. McDaniel, K. (2010a). Being and almost nothingness. Nous, 44, 628–649.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. McDaniel, K. (2010b). A return to the analogy of being. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 81, 688–717.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. McDaniel, K. (2017). The fragmentation of being. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. McSweeney, M. M. (forthcoming). Following logical realism where it leads. Philosophical Studies, pp. 1–23.Google Scholar
  36. Melia, J. (2000). Weaseling away the indispensibility argument. Mind, 109, 455–480.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Oliver, A. (1996). The metaphysics of properties. Mind, 105, 1–80.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Pickel, B., & Mantegani, N. (2012). A Quinean critique of Ostrich nominalism. Philosophers’ Imprint 12.Google Scholar
  39. Prior, A. N., & Fine, K. (1977). Worlds, times, and selves. London: Duckworth.Google Scholar
  40. Putnam, H. (1977). Realism and reason. Proceedings of the American Philosophical Association, 50, 483–498.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Quine, W. V. O. (1951a). Ontology and ideology. Philosophical Studies, 2, 11–15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Quine, W. V. O. (1951b). Two dogmas of empiricism. Philosophical Review, 60, 20–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Quine, W. V. O. (1953). Three grades of modal involvement. In Proceedings of the 11th international congress of philosophy, (vol. 14, pp. 65–81). Amsterdam: North-Holland.Google Scholar
  44. Quine, W. V. O. (1956). Quantifiers and propositional attitudes. Journal of Philosophy, 53, 177–187.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. Quine, W. V. O. (1960). Variables explained away. Proceedings of the American Philosophy Society, 104, 343–347.Google Scholar
  46. Rayo, A. (2013). The construction of logical space. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. Schaffer, J. (2014). What not to multiply without necessity. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 93, 644–664.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  48. Schwarz, W. (2014). Against magnetism. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 92, 17–36.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  49. Shapiro, S. (1993). Modality and ontology. Mind, 102, 455–481.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  50. Sider, T. (2001). Four-dimensionalism: An ontology of persistence and time. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  51. Sider, T. (2011). Writing the book of the world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  52. Sider, T. (2013). Replies to Dorr, Fine, and Hirsch. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 87, 733–754.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  53. Sullivan, M. (2016). An A-theory without tense operators. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 46, 735–758.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  54. Tahko, T. E. (2016). An introduction to metametaphysics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  55. Tallant, J. (2009). Ontological cheats just might prosper. Analysis, 69, 422–430.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  56. Tallant, J., & Ingram, D. (2015). Nefarious presentism. Philosophical Quarterly, 65, 355–371.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  57. Thomasson, A. L. (2017). Metaphysical disputes and metalinguistic negotiation. Analytic Philosophy, 58, 1–28.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  58. Torrengo, G. (2014). Ostrich presentism. Philosophical Studies, 170, 255–276.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  59. Torza, A. (2017). Ideology in a desert landscape. Philosophical Issues, 27, 383–406.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  60. Turner, Jason. (2010). Ontological pluralism. Journal of Philosophy, 107, 5–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  61. Turner, J. (2016). The facts in logical space: A tractarian ontology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  62. van Inwagen, P. (1998). Meta-ontology. Erkenntnis, 48, 233–250.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  63. van Inwagen, P. (2008). Quine’s 1946 lecture on nominalism. In Oxford studies in metaphysics, (Vol. 4, pp. 125–142). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  64. Weatherson, B. (2003). What good are counterexamples? Philosophical Studies, 115, 1–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  65. Williams, J. R. G. (2015). Lewis on reference and eligibility. In B. Loewer & J. Schaffer (Eds.), A companion to David Lewis, chapter 23 (pp. 367–381). London: Wiley-Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  66. Wilson, J. (2011). Much Ado about ‘Something’. Analysis, 71, 172–188.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  67. Zimmerman, D. W. (2005). The A-theory of time, the B-theory of time, and ‘taking tense seriously’. Dialectica, 59, 401–457.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature B.V. 2019

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.School of PhilosophyWuhan UniversityWuhanPeople’s Republic of China

Personalised recommendations