Skip to main content
Log in

Belief, credence, and evidence

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

I explore how rational belief and rational credence relate to evidence. I begin by looking at three cases where rational belief and credence seem to respond differently to evidence: cases of naked statistical evidence, lotteries, and hedged assertions. I consider an explanation for these cases, namely, that one ought not form beliefs on the basis of statistical evidence alone, and raise worries for this view. Then, I suggest another view that explains how belief and credence relate to evidence. My view focuses on the possibilities that the evidence makes salient. I argue that this makes better sense of the difference between rational credence and rational belief than other accounts.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See Jackson (forthcominga) for why the relationship between belief and credence is an important epistemological question.

  2. Buchak (2014), Staffel (2015), Smith (2010).

  3. Buchak (2014). See also Cohen (1977), Thomson (1986), Colyvan et al. (2001).

  4. Kyburg (1961), Nelkin (2000), Hawthrone (2003), Collins (2006), Staffel (2015), Kelp (2017), Horgan (2017).

  5. See Cohen (2010: p. 663) and Plantinga (1993a: pp. vii–viii, 1993b: pp. 132–161).

  6. A note on terminology: people often use the phrase “degrees of belief” to refer to a mental state that comes in degrees and in some sense, represents the world. I think such a mental state exists, but for our purposes, I call that “credence,” which I contrast with belief, a categorical state. One might prefer to use phrases like “partial belief” or “degrees of belief” instead of credence, and then call what I call belief “categorical belief.” I am not necessarily opposed to this, but given that some have argued that beliefs do not come in degrees (see Moon (2017)), my terminology is more ecumenical.

  7. Schwitzgebel (2015).

  8. Buchak (2014: p. 286). See also Holton (2014), Greco (2015).

  9. Weatherson (2005), Wedgwood (2012), Ross and Schroeder (2014), and Locke (2014) all have views on which some kind of treating-as-true condition is necessary for belief.

  10. See Nagel (2010: p. 418), Ross and Schroder (2014: pp. 275–277). One worry for this claim is that this is inconsistent with the threshold view of belief, on which belief that p is a high credence in p above some threshold (less than 1). However, those who hold to the threshold view could embrace this claim by maintaining that a credence’s meeting the threshold gives the attitude additional properties, which makes it function like a belief and causes the agent to close off possibilities (see Weisberg forthcoming: p. 22). Nonetheless, those sympathetic to the threshold view of belief will almost certainly disagree with my verdicts about the cases in section III, as in those cases, one’s credence in p can get arbitrarily close to one, yet one ought not believe p. In this, my assumptions about belief and credence may be inconsistent with a threshold view of belief.

  11. See Ramsey (1926), Jeffrey (1965), de Finetti (1990).

  12. Jeffrey (1965: p. 60).

  13. For objections to the view that credences are reducible to and/or measurable by betting behavior, see Foley (1993: ch. 4), Plantinga (1993b: ch. 6), Christensen (2004: 5.2), Hajek and Eriksson (2007), and Steffánson (2017).

  14. For more on the view that belief is credence 1, see Levi (1991), Roorda (1995), Wedgwood (2012), Clarke (2013), Greco (2015), Dodd (2016).

  15. See Enoch et al. (2012), Bloom-Tillmann (2015, 2017), and Di Bello (Forthcoming).

  16. Buchak (2014). For earlier discussions of similar cases, see Thomson (1986) and Schauer (2003); this case originated with a real civil case from the 1940 s. Thanks to an anonymous referee.

  17. See Thomson (1986), Kaplan (1996), Smith (2010, 2016, forthcoming), Nelkin (2000), Enoch et al. (2012), Staffel (2015), Pasnau (2018).

  18. One might worry that the reason it seems impermissible to form such beliefs is not because of the nature of one’s evidence, but because of the moral stakes involved. See Bolinger (forthcoming). Thanks to Wes Siscoe. However, consider a case where I know either a man or a woman is wearing a hat, and I know that men are 10 × more likely to wear hats than women. It still seems like I shouldn't believe the man is wearing the hat merely on the basis of the statistic alone, even though nothing is at stake morally. Further, there aren’t high moral stakes in many versions of the lottery and hedged assertions, but those cases also don’t justify belief.

  19. See Staffel (2015). Horgan (2017) also maintains one ought not believe lottery propositions: “outright belief that one’s lottery ticket will lose does not seem epistemically justified, no matter how high are the odds against winning.” For other discussions of the lottery paradox, especially with respect to the relationship between belief and credence, see Kyburg (1961), Foley (1993: ch. 4), Christensen (2004: ch. 2), Sturgeon (2008), Nelkin (2000), Collins (2006), Kelp (2017).

  20. Hawthorne (2003: ch. 1).

  21. Staffel (2015). See Williamson (2000: p. 255).

  22. See Kelp (2017) for an additional argument that it is irrational to believe lottery propositions.

  23. Smith (2010: pp. 13–14).

  24. Smith does not explicitly note this because his focus is not on credence, but I take this to be uncontroversial. He does note that “the probability of P given E can reach any level (short, perhaps, of one) without one having justification for believing P” (17).

  25. Adler (2002: p. 42).

  26. Thanks to an anonymous referee.

  27. For discussion, see Enoch et al. (2012), Enoch and Fisher (2015), Bloom-Tillman (2015).

  28. Smith (2010, 2016, forthcoming).

  29. Smith (2010: pp. 15–19).

  30. Ibid, 17.

  31. Thanks to an anonymous referee.

  32. However, for a recent criticism of Smith, see Backes (forthcoming).

  33. See Buchak (2014), Thomson (1986), Kaplan (1996), Nelkin (2000).

  34. Staffel (2015: p. 1725).

  35. Thanks to John Keller.

  36. Thanks to an anonymous referee.

  37. For a discussion of related cases, see Smith (2016: pp. 109–120).

  38. However, it is plausible that the fact that you shouldn’t withhold belief here is because the statistical evidence is trumped by the testimonial evidence, so this case may not draw any sort of interesting contrast between belief and credence. Thanks to an anonymous referee.

  39. Thomson (1986), Kaplan (1996), Nelkin (2000).

  40. Thanks to an anonymous referee.

  41. For a similar criticism of the statistical evidence view, see Enoch and Fisher (2015: Part I). One might worry that ‘statistics’ in the limit are not merely statistical evidence, because they posit a necessary connection between two things. However, it is unclear why evidence’s drawing a necessary connection between two things precludes that evidence’s being statistical. For example, suppose someone claims that having blue hair causes cancer. You ask for some statistical evidence to support their claim, and they say “100% of people with blue hair have cancer.” This seems like an apt response. It would be odd to complain that this isn’t mere statistical evidence because the correlation is too tight; it is unclear that a perfect correlation precludes that connection’s being statistical. I am grateful to an anonymous referee for raising this objection.

  42. Thanks to Daniel Rubio and an anonymous referee.

  43. Thanks to an anonymous referee.

  44. See Buchak (2014: p. 301).

  45. Ibid, 295.

  46. Thanks to an anonymous referee.

  47. See Buchak (2014: p. 301) on the problem of defining statistical evidence.

  48. Thanks to Blake Roeber. See Ross and Schroder (2014: p. 276).

  49. However, there are exceptions to this. Someone uttering “That is a zebra, not a cleverly painted mule” may make salient the possibility it is not a zebra, and thus count as C-evidence, and thus not justify belief. Thanks to an anonymous referee.

  50. For this reason, agents who fail to alter their beliefs on the basis of C-evidence will not be susceptible to the base rate fallacy. They will alter their credences in accord with the base rates, and bet accordingly. For more on the base rate fallacy see Kahneman (2011: ch. 14); for a response to Kahneman, see Feldman (1988: pp. 85–86).

  51. Thanks to Lara Buchak. See Locke (2014), Tang (2015), Moon (2018).

  52. Lewis (1996: p. 559). See especially Lewis’s “Rule of Attention.” See also Stalnaker (2002), Fantl and McGrath (2010: pp. 55–58).

  53. Thanks to Alan Hajek.

  54. Thanks to Ben Lennertz and Andrew Moon.

  55. This raises an interesting question: given your irrational paranoia, should you believe your partner is at the store? A larger project that involved both rational and irrational agents would say something about this question. More generally, it would discuss agents who respond to their evidence in less-than-ideal ways, either because they fail to consider possibilities they ought to pay attention to (someone being careless or thoughtless), or because they consider possibilities they ought not consider (an overly neurotic, anxious person). It might be the case that the neurotic person ought not to form as many beliefs as the person who is responding normally to evidence, because the anxious person’s evidence would make the possibility they are wrong more salient. However, what doxastic attitudes irrational agents ought to form in response to their evidence is ultimately beyond the scope of this paper.

  56. Thanks to Fritz Warfield.

  57. Note also that if pragmatic encroachment occurs, then a change in stakes might cause a change is what possibilities ought to be salient for an agent, and thus affect what that agent should believe. However, I remain neutral on whether stakes affect what is salient for rational agents.

  58. Collins (2006) also argues that the salience of the possibility of error does important work in the lottery paradox, but his application is to knowledge, rather than rational belief. He suggests the following necessary condition on knowledge to explain lottery cases, which nicely complements my account: “If there is some possibility that is very close to actuality that p is false, and to which S assigns a non-zero probability, then no matter how subjectively improbable this possibility is, S doesn’t know that p.” For a related discussion about the relationship between lotteries, statistical evidence, and knowledge, see Nelkin (2000).

  59. Staffel (2015: pp. 5–7). See also Hawthorne (2003: ch. 1).

  60. For instance: suppose we are trying to figure out what time it is, and there is a far-away, blurry clock (with hands), that makes it look roughly like it is 5:30 but it could also be 4:30 or 6:30. This would be some evidence that it is 5:30, but the nature of the perception should cause us to pay attention to the fact that we might be wrong; it would be natural to classify a blurry perception of this clock as C-evidence. For more on how perception might probabilistic, see Wedgwood (forthcoming).

  61. See DeRose (1995: p. 24), Schaffer (2004).

  62. Buchak (2014: p. 292).

  63. Thanks to Fritz Warfield.

  64. See especially Staffel (2017, Forthcominga), and also Lin (2013), Lin and Kelly (2012), Wedgwood (2012), Smithies (2012: p. 278), Tang (2015), Weatherson (2016), Staffel (Forthcomingb).

  65. See Ross and Schroeder (2014), especially the last section, “Historical Postscript.”

  66. I apply this view to questions about the rationality of faith in Jackson (forthcomingb).

  67. Thanks to Andrew Moon, Blake Roeber, Fritz Warfield, John Keller, Martin Smith, Renee Bolinger, Greta Turnbull, Wes Siscoe, Calum Miller, Lara Buchak, Alan Hajek, Jeff Tolly, Ben Lennertz, Ting Lau, Anne Jeffery, Nevin Climenhaga, Dustin Crummett, Ross Jensen, Rebecca Chan, Julia Staffel, Robert Audi, Lizzie Fricker, Daniel Nolan, the Doxastic Voluntarism seminar and the epistemology reading group at Notre Dame, and audiences at the 2016 St. Thomas Summer Seminar, 2016 Society for Christian Philosophers Eastern Regional Meeting, the 2016 Indiana Philosophical Association, the 2017 Philosopher’s Cocoon Conference, and three anonymous referees from this journal for helpful comments that improved this paper in many ways.

References

  • Adler, J. (2002). Belief’s own ethics. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Backes, M. (Forthcoming). Normalcy, justification, and the easy-defeat problem. Philosophical Studies. Available at: https://link.springer.com/article/10.1007/s11098-018-1155-y. Accessed 28 Sept 2018.

  • Bloom-Tillman, M. (2015). Sensitivity, causality, and statistical evidence in courts of law. Thought, 4, 2.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bloom-Tillman, M. (2017). ‘More likely than not’—knowledge first and the role of statistical evidence in courts of law. In A. Carter, E. Gordon, & B. Jarvis (Eds.), Knowledge first. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bolinger, R. J. (Forthcoming). The rational impermissibility of accepting (some) racial generalizations. Synthese. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-1809-5. Accessed 28 Sept 2018.

  • Buchak, L. (2014). Belief, credence, and norms. Philosophical Studies, 169(2), 285–311.

    Google Scholar 

  • Christensen, D. (2004). Putting logic in its place. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clarke, R. (2013). Belief is credence one (in context). Philosopher’s Imprint, 13, 1–18.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, J. (1977). The probable and the provable. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, J. (2010). Rationality. In J. Dancy, E. Sosa, & M. Steup (Eds.), A companion to epistemology. Hoboken: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collins, J. (2006). Lotteries and the close shave principle. In S. Hetherington (Ed.), Aspects of knowing. New York: Elsevier Science.

    Google Scholar 

  • Colyvan, M., Regan, H. M., & Ferson, S. (2001). Is it a crime to belong to a reference class?. Journal of Political Philosophy, 9(2), 168–181.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Finetti, B. (1990). Theory of probability (Vol. I) (first edition 1974). New York: Wiley.

  • DeRose, K. (1995). Solving the skeptical problem. The Philosophical Review, 104, 1.

    Google Scholar 

  • Di Bello, M. (Forthcoming). Trial by statistics: Is a high probability of guilt enough to convict? Mind. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1093/mind/fzy026.

  • Dodd, D. (2016). Belief and certainty. Synthese, 194(11), 4597–4621.

    Google Scholar 

  • Enoch, D., & Fisher, T. (2015). Sense and sensitivity: Epistemic and instrumental approaches to statistical evidence. Stanford Law Review, 67, 557–611.

    Google Scholar 

  • Enoch, D., Spectre, L., & Fisher, T. (2012). Statistical evidence, sensitivity, and the value of knowledge. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 40, 3.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fantl, J., & McGrath, M. (2010). Knowledge in an uncertain world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, R. (1988). Having evidence. In D. F. Austin (Ed.), Philosophical analysis. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foley, R. (1993). Working without a net. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greco, D. (2015). How I learned to stop worrying and love probability 1. Philosophical Perspectives, 29, 179–201.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hajek, A., & Eriksson, L. (2007). What are degrees of belief? Studia Logica, 86, 2.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawthrone, J. (2003). Knowledge and lotteries. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holton, R. (2014). Intention as a model for belief. In M. Vargas & G. Yaffe (Eds.), Rational and social agency: Essays on the philosophy of Michael Bratman. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horgan, T. (2017). Troubles for bayesian formal epistemology. Res Philosophica, 94(2), 233–255.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, E. (Forthcominga). Belief and credence: Why the attitude-type matters. Philosophical Studies. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-018-1136-1. Accessed 28 Sept 2018.

  • Jackson, E. (Forthcomingb). Belief, credence, and faith. Religious Studies. Available at: http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/S0034412518000446. Accessed 28 Sept 2018.

  • Jeffrey, R. (1965). The logic of decision. (Second edition 1983). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

  • Kahneman, D. (2011). Thinking fast and slow. New York: Farrar, Straus, and Giroux.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, M. (1996). Decision theory as philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelp, C. (2017). Lotteries and justification. Synthese, 194, 1233–1244.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kyburg, H. E. (1961). Probability and the logic of rational belief. Middletown: Wesleyan University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levi, I. (1991). The fixation of belief and its undoing: Changing beliefs through inquiry. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1996). Elusive knowledge. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 74, 4.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lin, H. (2013). Foundations of everyday practical reasoning. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 42, 831–862.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lin, H., & Kelly, K. (2012). Propositional reasoning that tracks probabilistic reasoning. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 41, 957–981.

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, D. (2014). The decision theoretic Lockean thesis. Inquiry, 57, 1.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moon, A. (2017). Beliefs do not come in degrees. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 47(6), 1–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moon, A. (2018). The nature of doubt and a new puzzle about belief, doubt, and confidence. Synthese, 195(4), 1827–1848.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, J. (2010). Epistemic anxiety and adaptive invariantism. Philosophical Perspectives, 24(1), 407–435.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nelkin, D. (2000). The lottery paradox, knowledge, and rationality. The Philosophical Review, 109, 3.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pasnau, R. (2018). Belief in a fallen world. Res Philosophica, 95(3), 531–559.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, A. (1993a). Warrant and proper function. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, A. (1993b). Warrant: The current debate. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramsey, F. (1926). Truth and probability. Reprinted in The foundations of mathematics and other logical essays, ed. R. B. Braithwaite. (1950). London: The Humanities Press.

  • Roorda, J. (1995). Revenge of Wolfman: A probabilistic explication of full belief. Available at: https://www.princeton.edu/~bayesway/pu/Wolfman.pdf. Accessed 28 Sept 2018.

  • Ross, J., & Schroeder, M. (2014). Belief, credence, and pragmatic encroachment. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 88(2), 259–288.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2004). From contextualism to contrastivism. Philosophical Studies, 119, 73–103.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schauer, F. (2003). Profiles, probabilities, and stereotypes. Cambridge: Belknap Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwitzgebel, E. (2015). Belief. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Available at: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/belief/. Accessed 28 Sept 2018.

  • Smith, M. (2010). What else justification could be. Nous, 44, 1.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, M. (2016). Between probability and certainty: What justifies belief. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, M. (Forthcoming). When does evidence suffice for conviction?. Mind. Available at: https://academic.oup.com/mind/advance-article/doi/10.1093/mind/fzx026/4555414. Accessed 28 Sept 2018.

  • Smithies, D. (2012). The normative role of knowledge. Nous, 46, 265–288.

    Google Scholar 

  • Staffel, J. (2015). Beliefs, buses, and lotteries: Why rational belief can’t be stably high credence. Philosophical Studies, 173(7), 1721–1734.

    Google Scholar 

  • Staffel, J. (2017). Accuracy for believers. In Episteme, book symposium on Pettigrew’s accuracy and the laws of credence (Vol. 14(1), pp. 39–48).

  • Staffel, J. (Forthcominga). How do beliefs simplify reasoning? Nous. Available at: https://doi.org/10.1111/nous.12254. Accessed 28 Sept 2018.

  • Staffel, J. (Forthcomingb). Attitudes in active reasoning. In M. B. Jackson & B. B. Jackson (Eds.), Reasoning: New essays on theoretical and practical thinking. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Stalnaker, R. (2002). Common ground. Linguistics and Philosophy, 25, 701–721.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steffánson, H. O. (2017). What is ‘Real’ in probabilism? Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 95(3), 573–587.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sturgeon, S. (2008). Reason and the grain of belief. Nous, 42, 139–165.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tang, W. H. (2015). Belief and cognitive limitations. Philosophical Studies, 172, 249–260.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomson, J. (1986). Liability and individualized evidence. Law and Contemporary Problems, 49(3), 199–219.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weatherson, B. (2005). Can we do without pragmatic encroachment? In Philosophical Perspectives, 19(1), 417–443

    Google Scholar 

  • Weatherson, B. (2016). Games, beliefs and credences. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 92, 209–236.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wedgwood, R. (Forthcoming). A probabilistic epistemology of perceptual belief. Philosophical Issues. Available at: https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/abs/10.1111/phis.12130. Accessed 28 Sept 2018.

  • Wedgwood, R. (2012). Outright belief. Dialectica, 66, 3.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, J. (Forthcoming). Belief in psyontology. Philosopher’s Imprint. Available at: http://jonathanweisberg.org/pdf/Psyontology.pdf. Accessed 28 Sept 2018.

  • Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Elizabeth Jackson.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Jackson, E. Belief, credence, and evidence. Synthese 197, 5073–5092 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-01965-1

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-01965-1

Keywords

Navigation