Skip to main content
Log in

A partial consequence account of truthlikeness

  • S.I.: LogPerSciCog
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Popper’s original definition of truthlikeness relied on a central insight: that truthlikeness combines truth and information, in the sense that a proposition is closer to the truth the more true consequences and the less false consequences it entails. As intuitively compelling as this definition may be, it is untenable, as proved long ago; still, one can arguably rely on Popper’s intuition to provide an adequate account of truthlikeness. To this aim, we mobilize some classical work on partial entailment in defining a new measure of truthlikeness which satisfies a number of desiderata. The resulting account has some interesting and surprising connections with other accounts on the market, thus shedding new light on current attempts of systematizing different approaches to verisimilitude.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Of course, this distinction parallels the familiar one between two equivalent ways of expressing sentences in formal languages, namely, the one between conjunctive and disjunctive normal forms. As immaterial as this distinction may be from a purely logical point of view, it can have significant implications for the formal analysis of epistemological concepts, as already Carnap (1950, secs. 72–73, especially p. 407) observed.

  2. In that paper, we introduced measure measure \( vs _{b}\) in the more general form \( vs _{b}(h)= cont _{T}(h) - \phi cont _{F}(h)\), where \(\phi >0\) expresses the relative weight of truth and falsity in assessing truthlikeness. Here, we shall only consider the special case \(\phi =1\). The label “contrast measure” refers to Amos Tversky’s “feature contrast” model of similarity between psychological stimuli, to which our measure is inspired.

  3. Note that here we could consider, as we did in the original account (Cevolani et al. 2011), a more general form of measure \( vs _{}\)—i.e., \( inf _{T}(h) - \phi inf _{F}(h)\)—where parameter \(\phi >0\) weighs the total amount of false information provided by h. In light of Theorem 1 from the next section, this would invite for a comparison between this weighted measure and Oddie’s weighted average measure of truthlikeness (Oddie 2013, p. 1663). We leave this issue to another occasion.

  4. The general formula for calculating the truthlikeness of disjunctions with both true and false literals is \(\frac{v}{k}\times \frac{(n-k+1)!}{n!})\), where k is the total number of disjuncts, v is the number of true disjuncts, and n is the number of atomic propositions of the language (Schurz and Weingartner 2010, p. 431).

  5. One may note that conjunction and disjunctions are “dual” to each other in the sense that a true conjunction is also “completely true” (but a false conjunction doesn’t need to be completely false) whereas a false disjunction is also “completely false” (but a true disjunction doesn’t need to be completely true).

  6. In addition, also the measures discussed in Cevolani et al. (2011, 2013), on which measure \( vs _{}\) is based, clearly belong to the conjunctive, consequence-based category, even if they are only defined for so-called conjunctive theories (cf. Sect. 3).

References

  • Carnap, R. (1950). Logical foundations of probability. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Second revised edition: 1962.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cevolani, G. (2016). Carnapian truthlikeness. Logic Journal of the IGPL, 24(4), 542–556.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cevolani, G. (2017). Truthlikeness and the problem of measure sensitivity. In M. Massimi, J.-W. Romeijn, & G. Schurz (Eds.), EPSA15 selected papers (pp. 257–271). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Cevolani, G., Crupi, V., & Festa, R. (2011). Verisimilitude and belief change for conjunctive theories. Erkenntnis, 75(2), 183–202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cevolani, G., Festa, R., & Kuipers, T. A. F. (2013). Verisimilitude and belief change for nomic conjunctive theories. Synthese, 190(16), 3307–3324.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crupi, V., & Tentori, K. (2013). Confirmation as partial entailment: A representation theorem in inductive logic. Journal of Applied Logic, 11(4), 364–372.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuipers, T. A. F. (1987). A structuralist approach to truthlikeness. In T. A. F. Kuipers (Ed.), What is closer-to-the-truth? (pp. 79–99). Amsterdam: Rodopi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuipers, T. A. F. (2000). From Instrumentalism to constructive realism. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, D. (1974). Popper’s qualitative theory of verisimilitude. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 25(2), 166–177.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, D. (1978). On distance from the truth as a true distance. In J. Hintikka, I. Niiniluoto, & E. Saarinen (Eds.), Essays on mathematical and philosophical logic (pp. 415–435). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Niiniluoto, I. (1987). Truthlikeness. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Niiniluoto, I. (1998). Verisimilitude: The third period. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 49(1), 1–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Niiniluoto, I. (1999). Critical Scientific Realism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Niiniluoto, I. (2003). Content and likeness definitions of truthlikeness. In J. Hintikka (Ed.), Philosophy and logic: In search of the polish tradition. Essays in honor of Jan Woleński on the occasion of his 60th birthday (pp. 27–35). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oddie, G. (1986). Likeness to truth. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Oddie, G. (2013). The content, consequence and likeness approaches to verisimilitude: Compatibility, trivialization, and underdetermination. Synthese, 190(9), 1647–1687.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oddie, G. (2016). Truthlikeness. In E . N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Frankfurt: Winter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R. (1963). Conjectures and refutations: The growth of scientific knowledge. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roche, W. (2018). Is there a place in Bayesian confirmation theory for the reverse Matthew effect? Synthese, 195, 1631–1648.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W . C. (1969). Partial entailment as a basis for inductive logic. In N. Rescher (Ed.), Essays in honor of Carl G. Hempel (pp. 47–82). Dordrecht: Reidel.

  • Schurz, G. (2011). Verisimilitude and belief revision. With a focus on the relevant element account. Erkenntnis, 75(2), 203–221.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schurz, G., & Weingartner, P. (1987). Verisimilitude defined by relevant consequence-elements. In T. A. F. Kuipers (Ed.), What is closer-to-the-truth? (pp. 47–77). Amsterdam: Rodopi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schurz, G., & Weingartner, P. (2010). Zwart and Franssen’s impossibility theorem holds for possible-world-accounts but not for consequence-accounts to verisimilitude. Synthese, 172, 415–436.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tichý, P. (1974). On Popper’s definitions of verisimilitude. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 25(2), 155–160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zwart, S. D. (2001). Refined verisimilitude. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Zwart, S. D., & Franssen, M. (2007). An impossibility theorem for verisimilitude. Synthese, 158(1), 75–92.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We would like to thank Vincenzo Crupi, Theo Kuipers, Ilkka Niiniluoto, and Luca Tambolo for very useful discussions on the topics of this paper, and three anonymous reviewers for detailed critical comments on a previous draft. Gustavo Cevolani gratefully acknowledges financial support from the Italian Ministry of Education, University and Research (MIUR) through the FFABR 2017 grant.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Gustavo Cevolani.

A Proofs

A Proofs

In the following, we prove all the main claims in the paper.

  • Measure\( vs _{}\)meets P5. Let be h and g true, conjunctive propositions, i.e., conjunctions of true literals. It is then clear that \( inf _{F}(h)= inf _{F}(g)=0\), since both h and g partially entail no basic falsehoods. Moreover, \( inf _{T}(h)=| B _{T}(h)|/n\) and \( inf _{T}(g)=| B _{T}(g)|/n\), since both h and g “fully” entail each of their own conjuncts. Suppose now that h entails g. This means that \( B _{T}(h)\supset { B _{T}(g)}\), i.e., that h adds to g some true conjunct, and hence \( inf _{T}(h)>{ inf _{T}(g)}\). It follows that \( vs _{}(h)= inf _{T}(h)> inf _{T}(g)= vs _{}(g)\), i.e., that P5 is satisfied.

  • Measure\( vs _{av}\)meets P5. If h is a conjunctive proposition, all constituents in the range of h are “completions” of h, in the sense that they all agree with h on each of its conjuncts. Now suppose that h and g are true, conjunctive propositions such that h is logically stronger than g. This means that h entails all (true) conjuncts of g and also some other true conjunct. In turn, this means that, by the closeness measure \(\lambda _{}\), each constituent in the range of h is closer to the truth than each constituent in that of g. It follows that the average truthlikeness is greater for h than for g, i.e., that P5 is satisfied.

  • Theorem 1: Measures\( vs _{}\)and\( vs _{av}\)are ordinally equivalent. In the following, we shall use b to denote arbitrary an basic proposition (literal) of \(\mathcal {L}_{n}\), w to denote an arbitrary constituent, and t for the true constituent. Moreover, in order to simplify notation, we shall write \( r (h)\) for \(| R (h)|\), i.e., for the number of constituents entailing h.

    We start by noting that, for any h and b, \( m _{}(\lnot b|h) = 1- m _{}(b|h)\); from this and the definition of \( inf _{}\) it follows that \( inf _{}(h,\lnot b)=- inf _{}(h,b)\). Accordingly, \( vs _{}\) can be rewritten as follows:

    $$\begin{aligned} \begin{array}{lcl} vs _{}(h) &{} = &{} inf _{T}(h) - inf _{F}(h)\\ &{} = &{} \frac{1}{n}\times \sum \limits _{b\in PB _{T}(h)} inf _{}(h,b) - \frac{1}{n}\times \sum \limits _{b\in PB _{F}(h)} inf _{}(h,b) \\ &{} = &{} \frac{1}{n}\times \sum \limits _{b\in PB _{}(h): t\vDash b} inf _{}(h,b) - \frac{1}{n}\times \sum \limits _{b\in PB _{}(h): t\vDash \lnot b} inf _{}(h,b) \\ &{} = &{} \frac{1}{n}\times \sum \limits _{b\in PB _{}(h): t\vDash b} inf _{}(h,b) - \frac{1}{n}\times \sum \limits _{b\not \in PB _{}(h): t\vDash b}- inf _{}(h, b) \\ &{} = &{} \frac{1}{n}\times \sum \limits _{b\in PB _{}(h): t\vDash b} inf _{}(h,b) + \frac{1}{n}\times \sum \limits _{b\not \in PB _{}(h): t\vDash b} inf _{}(h, b) \\ &{} = &{} \frac{1}{n}\times \sum \limits _{b: t\vDash b} inf _{}(h,b)\\ \end{array} \end{aligned}$$

    Moreover, by definition of \( inf _{}\):

    $$\begin{aligned} \begin{array}{lcl} vs _{}(h) &{} = &{} \frac{1}{n}\times \sum \limits _{b: t\vDash b} inf _{}(h,b)\\ &{} = &{} \frac{1}{n}\times \sum \limits _{b: t\vDash b} \left( 2( m _{}(b|h)-\frac{1}{2})\right) \\ &{} = &{} \frac{2}{n}\times \sum \limits _{b: t\vDash b} \left( m _{}(b|h)-\frac{1}{2}\right) \\ &{} = &{} \frac{2}{n}\left( \sum \limits _{b: t\vDash b} m _{}(b|h)-\frac{n}{2}\right) \\ &{} = &{} \frac{2}{n}\sum \limits _{b: t\vDash b} m _{}(b|h) - 1\\ \end{array} \end{aligned}$$
    (1)

    As for the average measure, note that, by definition of \( vs _{av}{h}\), of \(\lambda _{}(w,t)\), and of \( B _{T}(w)\):

    $$\begin{aligned} \begin{array}{lcl} vs _{av}(h) &{} = &{} \frac{1}{ r (h)} \sum \limits _{w:w\vDash h} \lambda _{}(w,t)\\ &{} = &{} \frac{1}{ r (h)} \sum \limits _{w:w\vDash h} \frac{| B _{T}(w)|}{n}\\ \end{array} \end{aligned}$$

    Moreover, since for any constituent w, \( r (b\wedge w)\) is either 1 (if \(w\vDash b\)) or 0 (if \(w\nvDash b\)), \(| B _{T}(w)|\) can be written as \(\sum _{b:t\vDash b} r (b\wedge w)\). Accordingly,

    $$\begin{aligned} \begin{array}{lcl} vs _{av}(h) &{} = &{} \frac{1}{ r (h)} \sum \limits _{w:w\vDash h} \frac{1}{n}\sum _{b:t\vDash b} r (b\wedge w)\\ &{} = &{} \frac{1}{n} \sum _{w:w\vDash h} \sum \limits _{b:t\vDash b} \frac{ r (b\wedge w)}{ r (h)}\\ \end{array} \end{aligned}$$

    Now note that \( m _{}(b|h)=\frac{ m _{}(b\wedge h)}{ m _{}(h)}=\frac{ r (b\wedge h)}{ r (h)}\) by definition. In turn, \( r (b\wedge h)\) can be written as \(\sum _{w:w\vDash h} r (b\wedge w)\). It follows that \( m _{}(b|h)=\sum _{w:w\vDash h} \frac{ r (b\wedge w)}{ r (h)}\) and hence that:

    $$\begin{aligned} \begin{array}{lcl} vs _{av}(h) &{} = &{} \frac{1}{n} \sum \limits _{b:t\vDash b} m _{}(b|h)\\ \end{array} \end{aligned}$$
    (2)

    From the comparison of Eqs. 1 and 2 above, it follows that:

    $$\begin{aligned} vs _{}(h) = 2\times vs _{av}(h) - 1 \end{aligned}$$

    and hence that measures \( vs _{}\) and \( vs _{av}\) are ordinally equivalent, which completes the proof of Theorem 1.

  • Measure\( vs _{}\)meets P7. We start by stating the following results, which will be useful in the following. First, if h is a disjunction of k literals, the amount of information provided by h on each of its disjunct b is:

    $$\begin{aligned} \begin{array}{lcl} inf _{}(h,b) &{} = &{} 2\times \left( m _{}(b|h) - \frac{1}{2}\right) = 2\times \left( \frac{ m _{}(b\wedge h)}{ m _{}(h)} - \frac{1}{2}\right) \\ &{} = &{} 2\times \left( \frac{2^{n-1}}{2^n-2^{n-k}} - \frac{1}{2}\right) = \frac{1}{2^k - 1} \end{array} \end{aligned}$$
    (3)

    In fact, note that if b is a disjunct of h, then \(b\vDash h\) and \( m _{}(b\wedge h)= m _{}(b)=2^{n-1}\). Moreover, h is false only in those worlds where all k literals of h are false; since there are \(2^{n-k}\) such worlds, \( m _{}(h)=2^n-2^{n-k}\).

    Second, if h is either completely true or false, its truthlikeness only depends on the total number k of its disjunct and on the amount of information provided by h on each of them (as just calculated above). In fact:

    $$\begin{aligned} \begin{array}{l} \text {if }h\text { is completely true, then } vs _{}(h) = inf _{T}(h) = \frac{1}{n}\times \frac{k}{2^k - 1}\\ \text {if }h\text { is false, then } vs _{}(h) = - inf _{F}(h) = -\frac{1}{n}\times \frac{k}{2^k - 1}\\ \end{array} \end{aligned}$$
    (4)

    This is because if h is completely true (resp. false), then it entails no basic falsehoods (resp. truths), and hence \( inf _{F}(h)\) (resp. \( inf _{T}(h)\)) is zero.

    Finally, one should note that the factor \(\frac{k}{2^k - 1}\) appearing in the two expressions in 4 decreases for increasing k. To show this, we prove that increasing k by 1 (i.e., weakening h by the addition of one false disjunct) makes the above factor decrease:

    $$\begin{aligned} \begin{array}{rcll} \frac{k+1}{2^{k+1} - 1} &{}< &{} \frac{k}{2^k - 1} &{} \text {iff} \\ \left( {k+1}\right) \left( {2^k - 1}\right) &{}< &{} {k}\left( {2^{k+1} - 1}\right) &{} \text {iff} \\ 2^{k}-1 &{}< &{} k2^k &{} \text {iff} \\ 1-\frac{1}{2^{k}} &{} < &{} k &{} \end{array} \end{aligned}$$
    (5)

    Recalling that k is a positive integer (\(k\ge 1\)), the above inequality is always satisfied, which proves that \(\frac{k}{2^k - 1}\) decreases for increasing k.

    Now, coming back to P7, let be h and g two completely true disjunctions of literals such that \(h\vDash g\). This means that g weakens h by adding to it some true basic disjunct, in the sense that g has the form \(h\vee b\) for at least one b different from the disjuncts of h. Since the number k of disjuncts increases by moving from h to g, truthlikeness decreases by Eqs. 4 and 5 above, and then h is more verisimilar than g, which proves that \( vs _{}\) meets P7.

  • Measure\( vs _{}\)meets P8. Let be h and g completely false conjunctive propositions, i.e., conjunctions of false literals. It is then clear that \( inf _{T}(h)= inf _{T}(g)=0\), since both h and g partially entail no basic truths. Moreover, \( inf _{F}(h)=| B _{F}(h)|/n\) and \( inf _{F}(g)=| B _{F}(g)|/n\), since both h and g “fully” entail each of their own conjuncts. Suppose now that h entails g. This means that \( B _{F}(h)\supset { B _{F}(g)}\), i.e., that h adds to g some false conjunct, and hence that \( inf _{F}(h)>{ inf _{F}(g)}\). It follows in turn that \( vs _{}(h)=- inf _{F}(h)<- inf _{F}(g)= vs _{}(g)\), i.e., that P8 is satisfied.

  • Measure\( vs _{}\)meets P9. Let be h and g two false disjunctions of literals such that \(h\vDash g\). This means that g has a greater number of disjuncts than h (compare the proof that \( vs _{}\) meets P7 above). From Eqs. 4 and 5 above, it then follows that \( inf _{F}(g)< inf _{F}(h)\) and hence that \( vs _{}(g)=- inf _{F}(g)>- inf _{F}(h)= vs _{}(h)\), i.e., that g is more verisimilar than h, which proves that \( vs _{}\) meets P9.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Cevolani, G., Festa, R. A partial consequence account of truthlikeness. Synthese 197, 1627–1646 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-01947-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-01947-3

Keywords

Navigation