Advertisement

Synthese

pp 1–19 | Cite as

The structure of asymptotic idealization

  • Michael Strevens
S.I. : Infinite Idealizations in Science

Abstract

Robert Batterman and others have argued that certain idealizing explanations have an asymptotic form: they account for a state of affairs or behavior by showing that it emerges “in the limit”. Asymptotic idealizations are interesting in many ways, but is there anything special about them as idealizations? To understand their role in science, must we augment our philosophical theories of idealization? This paper uses simple examples of asymptotic idealization in population genetics to argue for an affirmative answer and proposes a general schema for asymptotic idealization, drawing on insights from Batterman’s treatment and from John Norton’s subsequent critique.

Keywords

Explanation Idealization Models Population genetics Asymptotic idealization Infinite idealization 

Notes

Acknowledgements

For invaluable discussion and feedback, thanks to Bob Batterman and John Norton, Kate Vredenburgh, the Research Triangle Philosophy of Science Reading Group, the audience at ISHPSSB 2013, and the anonymous reviewers at Synthese.

References

  1. Abrams, M. (2006). Infinite populations and counterfactual frequencies in evolutionary theory. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 37, 256–268.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Batterman, R. W. (2002). The devil in the details: Asymptotic reasoning in explanation, reduction, and emergence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  3. Batterman, R. W. (2010). On the explanatory role of mathematics in empirical science. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 61, 1–25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Belot, G. (2005). Whose devil? Which details? Philosophy of Science, 72, 128–153.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Edwards, A. W. F. (1977). Foundations of mathematical genetics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  6. Elgin, C. (2007). Understanding and the facts. Philosophical Studies, 132, 33–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Gillespie, J. H. (2004). Population genetics: A concise guide (2nd ed.). Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
  8. McMullin, E. (1985). Galilean idealization. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 16, 247–273.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Norton, J. D. (2012). Approximation and idealization: Why the difference matters. Philosophy of Science, 79, 207–232.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Pincock, C. (2012). Mathematics and scientific representation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Potochnik, A. (2017). Idealization and the aims of science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Ramsey, G. (2013). Driftability. Synthese, 190, 3909–3928.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Strevens, M. (2008). Depth: An account of scientific explanation. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  14. Strevens, M. (2017). How idealizations provide understanding. In S. R. Grimm, C. Baumberger, & S. Ammon (Eds.), Explaining understanding: New perspectives from epistemology and philosophy of science. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
  15. Wayne, A. (2012). Emergence and singular limits. Synthese, 184, 341–356.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Weinberg, S. (1992). Dreams of a final theory. New York: Pantheon.Google Scholar
  17. Weisberg, M. (2007). Three kinds of idealization. Journal of Philosophy, 104, 639–659.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Weisberg, M. (2013). Simulation and similarity: Using models to understand the world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V., part of Springer Nature 2017

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyNew York UniversityNew YorkUSA

Personalised recommendations