Advertisement

Synthese

pp 1–18 | Cite as

Ambiguous signals, partial beliefs, and propositional content

  • Rafael VenturaEmail author
Article
  • 143 Downloads

Abstract

As the content of propositional attitudes, propositions are usually taken to help explain the behavior of rational agents. However, a closer look at signaling games suggests otherwise: rational agents often acquire partial beliefs, and many of their signals are ambiguous. Signaling games also suggest that it is rational for agents to mix their behavior in response to partial beliefs and ambiguous signals. But as I show in this paper, propositions cannot help explain the mixing behavior of rational agents: to explain mixing behavior, we need a probabilistic notion of content. I also show that a probabilistic notion of content renders propositions explanatorily idle in the case of unambiguous signals and full beliefs as well. My suggestion is thus that we should abandon propositions in explanations of rational behavior and adopt instead a probabilistic notion of content. The notion of probabilistic content ultimately provides a simpler framework for explanations of rational behavior than the notion of propositional content.

Keywords

Signaling games Propositional content Ambiguous signal Partial belief 

Notes

Acknowledgements

I thank Alex Rosenberg, Karen Neander, Robert Brandon, and especially Carlotta Pavese for invaluable feedback on previous drafts of this paper, as well as three anonymous referees for their helpful comments. I also thank Hannah Read for her support. Funding was provided by Graduate School, Duke University.

References

  1. Birch, J. (2014). Propositional content in signalling systems. Philosophical Studies, 171(3), 493–512.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Bruner, J., O’Connor, C., Rubin, H., & Huttegger, S. M. (2014). David Lewis in the lab: Experimental results on the emergence of meaning. Synthese. doi: 10.1007/s11229-014-0535-x.Google Scholar
  3. Cai, H., & Wang, J. T.-Y. (2006). Overcommunication in strategic information transmission games. Games and Economic Behavior, 56(1), 7–36.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Crawford, V. P., & Sobel, J. (1982). Strategic information transmission. Econometrica: Journal of the Econometric Society, 50, 1431–1451.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Dickhaut, J. W., McCabe, K. A., & Mukherji, A. (1995). An experimental study of strategic information transmission. Economic Theory, 6(3), 389–403.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Dretske, F. (1981). Knowledge and the flow of information. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  7. Franke, M., & Correia, J. P. (2016). Vagueness and imprecise imitation in signaling games. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science. doi: 10.1093/bjps/axx002.Google Scholar
  8. Franke, M., Jäger, G., & Van Rooij, R. (2010). Vagueness, signaling and bounded rationality. In JSAI international symposium on artificial intelligence (pp. 45–59). Springer.Google Scholar
  9. Gee, N. R., & Harris, S. L. (2010). Homograph norms: An alternative approach to determining meaning dominance. Behavior research methods, 42(4), 976–986.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Godfrey-Smith, P. (2011). Signals: Evolution, learning, and information, by Brian Skyrms. Mind, 120(480), 1288–1297.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Godfrey-Smith, P., & Martínez, M. (2013). Communication and common interest. PLoS Computational Biology, 9(11), 1–6.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Haro, J., Ferré, P., Boada, R., & Demestre, J. (2016). Semantic ambiguity norms for 530 Spanish words. Applied Psycholinguistics. doi: 10.1017/S0142716416000266.Google Scholar
  13. Huttegger, S. M., Skyrms, B., Smead, R., & Zollman, K. J. (2010). Evolutionary dynamics of Lewis signaling games: Signaling systems vs. partial pooling. Synthese, 172(1), 177–191.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Huttegger, S. M., & Zollman, K. J. (2010). Dynamic stability and basins of attraction in the Sir Philip Sidney game. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B: Biological Sciences, 277(1689), 1915–1922.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Joyce, J. M. (2010). A defense of imprecise credences in inference and decision making. Philosophical Perspectives, 24(1), 281–323.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Lewis, D. (1969). Convention: A philosophical study. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  17. Maynard-Smith, J. (1991). Honest signalling: The Philip Sidney game. Animal Behaviour, 42(6), 1034–1035.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Moss, S. (2013). Epistemology formalized. Philosophical Review, 122(1), 1–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Navigli, R. (2009). Word sense disambiguation: A survey. ACM Computing Surveys (CSUR), 41(2), 10.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. O’Connor, C. (2014). The evolution of vagueness. Erkenntnis, 79(4), 707–727.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. O’Connor, C. (2015). Ambiguity is kinda good sometimes. Philosophy of Science, 82(1), 110–121.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Perea, A. (2012). Epistemic game theory: Reasoning and choice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Quine, W. V. (1934). Ontological remarks on the propositional calculus. Mind, 43(172), 472–476.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Rubin, H., Bruner, J., O’Connor, C., & Huttegger, S. M. (2016). Communication without the cooperative principle: A signaling experiment. Unpublished manuscript.Google Scholar
  25. Santana, C. (2014). Ambiguity in cooperative signaling. Philosophy of Science, 81(3), 398–422.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Scarantino, A. (2015). Information as a probabilistic difference maker. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 93(3), 419–443.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Serra-Garcia, M., Van Damme, E., & Potters, J. (2011). Hiding an inconvenient truth: Lies and vagueness. Games and Economic Behavior, 73(1), 244–261.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Skyrms, B. (2010). Signals: Evolution, learning, and information. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Staffel, J. (2013). Can there be reasoning with degrees of belief? Synthese, 190(16), 3535–3551.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Stalnaker, R. (1976). Propositions. In Issues in the philosophy of language (pp. 79–91).Google Scholar
  31. Stalnaker, R. (1978). Assertion. Syntax and Semantics, 9, 315–332.Google Scholar
  32. Stalnaker, R. (1984). Inquiry. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  33. Stalnaker, R. (2002). Common ground. Linguistics and philosophy, 25(5), 701–721.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Stalnaker, R. (2003). Ways a world might be: Metaphysical and anti-metaphysical essays. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Stegmann, U. E. (2009). A consumer-based teleosemantics for animal signals. Philosophy of Science, 76(5), 864–875.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Wagner, E. O. (2011). Deterministic chaos and the evolution of meaning. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 63(3), 547–575.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Wagner, E. O. (2013). The dynamics of costly signaling. Games, 4(2), 163–181.Google Scholar
  38. Zollman, K. J., Bergstrom, C. T., & Huttegger, S. M. (2012). Between cheap and costly signals: The evolution of partially honest communication. Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences. doi: 10.1098/rspb.2012.1878.

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2017

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Philosophy DepartmentDuke UniversityDurhamUSA

Personalised recommendations