Advertisement

Synthese

, Volume 195, Issue 4, pp 1779–1798 | Cite as

Metaphysical necessity dualism

  • Ben White
Article

Abstract

A popular response to the Exclusion Argument for physicalism maintains that mental events depend on their physical bases in such a way that the causation of a physical effect by a mental event and its physical base needn’t generate any problematic form of causal overdetermination, even if mental events are numerically distinct from and irreducible to their physical bases. This paper presents and defends a form of dualism that implements this response by using a dispositional essentialist view of properties to argue that the psychophysical laws linking mental events to their physical bases are metaphysically necessary. I show the advantages of such a position over an alternative form of dualism that merely places more “modal weight” on psychophysical laws than on physical laws. The position is then defended against the objection that it is inconsistent with dualism. Lastly, some suggestions are made as to how dualists might clarify the contribution that mental causes make to their physical effects.

Keywords

Mental causation Exclusion Argument Dualism Overdetermination Dispositional essentialism 

References

  1. Bennett, K. (2003). Why the exclusion problem seems intractable, and how, just maybe, to tract it. Noûs, 37, 471–497.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Bennett, K. (2008). Exclusion again. In J. Hohwy & J. Kallestrup (Eds.), Being reduced: New essays on reduction, explanation, and causation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  3. Bernstein, S. (2016). Overdetermination underdetermined. Erkenntnis, 81, 17–40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Bird, A. (2007). Nature’s metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Black, R. (2000). Against quidditism. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 78, 87–104.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Block, N. (1997). Anti-reductionism slaps back: Mental causation, reduction and supervenience. Philosophical Perspectives, 11, 107–132.Google Scholar
  7. Chalmers, D. (1996). The conscious mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  8. Clapp, L. (2001). Disjunctive properties: Multiple realizations. Journal of Philosophy, 98, 111–136.Google Scholar
  9. Corry, R. (2011). Can dispositional essences ground the laws of nature? Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 89, 263–275.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Dennett, D. (1995). The unimagined preposterousness of zombies. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 2, 322–326.Google Scholar
  11. Ellis, B., & Lierse, C. (1994). Dispositional essentialism. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 72, 27–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Funkhouser, E. (2002). Three varieties of causal overdetermination. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 83, 335–351.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Gibb, S. (2010). Closure principles and the laws of conservation of energy and momentum. Dialectica, 64, 363–384.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Kallestrup, J. (2006). The causal exclusion argument. Philosophical Studies, 131, 459–485.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Kim, J. (1989a). Mechanism, purpose, and explanatory exclusion. Philosophical Perspectives, 3, 77–108.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Kim, J. (1989b). The myth of non-reductive materialism. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 63, 31–47.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Kim, J. (1993). The nonreductivist’s trouble with mental causation. In J. Heil & A. Mele (Eds.), Mental causation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  18. Kim, J. (1998). Mind in a physical world. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  19. Kim, J. (2007). Causation and mental causation. In B. McLaughlin & J. Cohen (Eds.), Contemporary debates in philosophy of mind (pp. 227–242). Malden: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  20. Kripke, S. (1980). Naming and necessity. Harvard: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  21. Kroedel, T. (2013). Dualist mental causation and the exclusion problem. Noûs, 47, 1–19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Lowe, E. J. (2000). Causal closure principles and emergentism. Philosophy, 75, 571–585.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Lowe, E. J. (2009). Substance dualism? A non-cartesian approach. In R. Koons & G. Bealer (Eds.), The waning of materialism: New essays. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  24. Mellor, D. H. (1995). The facts of causation. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Menzies, P. (2003). The causal efficacy of mental states. In S. Walter & H.-D. Heckmann (Eds.), Physicalism and mental causation. Exeter: Imprint Academic.Google Scholar
  26. Merricks, T. (2001). Objects and persons. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Molnar, G. (2003). Powers: A study in metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  28. Mumford, S. (2004). Laws in nature. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Mumford, S. (2006). The ungrounded argument. Synthese, 149, 471–489.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Schaffer, J. (2003). Overdetermining causes. Philosophical Studies, 114, 23–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Shoemaker, S. (2001). Realization and mental causation. In C. Gillett & B. Loewer (Eds.), Physicalism and its discontents (pp. 23–33). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  32. Shoemaker, S. (2007). Physical realization. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Sider, T. (2003). What’s so bad about overdetermination? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 67, 719–726.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Sider, T. (2013). Against Parthood. In K. Bennett & D. W. Zimmerman (Eds.), Oxford studies in metaphysics (Vol. 8, pp. 237–293). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  35. Swoyer, C. (1982). The nature of natural laws. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 60, 203–223.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. White, B. (forthcoming). Conservation laws and interactionist dualism. Philosophical Quarterly. doi: 10.1093/pq/pqw054.
  37. Wilson, J. (1999). How superduper does a physicalist supervenience need to be? Philosophical Quarterly, 50, 33–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Wilson, J. (2005). Supervenience-based formulations of physicalism. Noûs, 39, 426–459.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Wilson, J. (2010). What is hume’s dictum, and why believe it? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 80, 595–637.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Wilson, J. (2011). Non-reductive realization and the powers-based subset strategy. The Monist, 94, 121–154.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Yablo, S. (1993). Is conceivability a guide to possibility? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 53, 1–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2017

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Temple UniversityPhiladelphiaUSA

Personalised recommendations