Synthese

, Volume 194, Issue 7, pp 2557–2580 | Cite as

Moderately naturalistic metaphysics

Article

Abstract

The present paper discusses different approaches to metaphysics and defends a specific, non-deflationary approach that nevertheless qualifies as scientifically-grounded and, consequently, as acceptable from the naturalistic viewpoint. By critically assessing some recent work on science and metaphysics, we argue that such a sophisticated form of naturalism, which preserves the autonomy of metaphysics as an a priori enterprise yet pays due attention to the indications coming from our best science, is not only workable but recommended.

Keywords

Metaphysics Naturalism Empiricism Modelling Theoretical virtues A priori A posteriori 

References

  1. Callender, C. (2011). Philosophy of science and metaphysics. In S. French & J. Saatsi (Eds.), The Continuum companion to the philosophy of science (pp. 33–54). London: Continuum.Google Scholar
  2. Dehmelt, H. (1989). Triton, ...Electron, ...Cosmon, ...: An infinite regression? In Proceedings of the National Academy of the Sciences USA (Vol. 86, pp. 8618–8619)Google Scholar
  3. Dyke, H., & Maclaurin, J. (2013). What shall we do with analytic metaphysics? A response to McLeod and Parsons. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 91, 179–182.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Fine, K. (1994). Essence and modality. In J. E. Tomberlin (Ed.), Philosophical perspectives, 8: Logic and language (pp. 1–16). Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview.Google Scholar
  5. Goldman, A. I. (2007). A program for ’Naturalizing’ Metaphysics, with application to the ontology of events. The Monist, 90(3), 457–479.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Goldman, A. I. (2015). Naturalizing metaphysics with the help of cognitive science. In K. Bennett & D. W. Zimmerman (Eds.), Oxford studies in metaphysics (Vol. 9, pp. 171–212). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Hooker, C. A. (1987). A realistic theory of science. Albany, NY: SUNY Press.Google Scholar
  8. Jackson, F. (1998). From metaphysics to ethics: A defence of conceptual analysis. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  9. Jenkins, C. S. (2014). Intuition, “Intuition”, concepts and the A priori. In A. R. Booth & D. P. Rowbottom (Eds.), Intuitions (pp. 91–115). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Ladyman, J. (2012). Science, metaphysics and method. Philosophical Studies, 160(1), 31–51.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Ladyman, J., Ross, D., Spurrett, D., & Collier, J. (2007). Every thing must go: Metaphysics naturalized. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Lowe, E. J. (2006). The four-category ontology. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  13. Lowe, E. J. (2008). Two notions of being: Entity and essence. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplements, 83(62), 23–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Lowe, E. J. (2011). The rationality of metaphysics. Synthese, 178, 99–109.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Lowe, E. J. (2012). What is the source of our knowledge of modal truths? Mind, 121, 919–950.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Lowe, E. J. (2014). Essence vs. intuition: An unequal contest. In A. R. Booth & D. P. Rowbottom (Eds.), Intuitions (pp. 256–268). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Maclaurin, J., & Dyke, H. (2012). What is analytic metaphysics for? Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 90, 291–306.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Maddy, P. (2007). Second philosophy: A naturalistic method. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. McLeod, M., & Parsons, J. (2013). Maclaurin and Dyke on analytic metaphysics. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 91, 173–178.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Melia, J. (2000). Weaseling away the indispensability argument. Mind, 109, 455–479.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Nolan, D. (2015). The A posteriori armchair. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 93(2), 211–231.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Paul, L. A. (2012). Metaphysics as modeling: The Handmaiden’s Tale. Philosophical Studies, 160, 1–29.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Ritchie, J. (2008). Understanding naturalism. Durham: Acumen.Google Scholar
  24. Roca-Royes, S. (2011). Modal knowledge and counterfactual knowledge. Logique et Analyse, 54, 537–552.Google Scholar
  25. Sider, T. (2011). Writing the book of the world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  26. Tahko, T. E. (2012). Counterfactuals and modal epistemology. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 86, 93–115.Google Scholar
  27. Tallant, J. (2013). Intuitions in physics. Synthese, 190(15), 2959–2980.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. van Fraassen, B. (2002). The empirical stance. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
  29. Williamson, T. (2007). The philosophy of philosophy. Oxford: Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2016

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of Philosophy, Communication and Visual ArtsUniversity of Rome ‘TRE’RomeItaly
  2. 2.Department of Philosophy, History, Culture and Art Studies, Theoretical PhilosophyUniversity of HelsinkiHelsinkiFinland

Personalised recommendations