1 The epistemic norms of practical reasoning

Intuitively, before the result of a lottery is announced, it seems inappropriate for me to sell my lottery ticket for a penny on the basis that I will lose, since I do not know that the ticket is a loser. In the same spirit, I can be criticized for not buying insurance in a situation in which I do not know that I will not get sick. On the other hand, if I know that my door is locked, it seems that there is nothing wrong for me not to come back and check whether it is locked. On the basis of similar intuitions about ordinary appraisals and criticisms of action, some philosophers have argued that practical reasoning is governed by a knowledge norm.Footnote 1 Consider a specific version of the norm, suggested by Hawthorne and Stanley (2008):

Reason-Knowledge Principle (RKP)

Where one’s choice is p-dependent, it is appropriate to treat the proposition that p as a reason for acting iff you know that p (578).Footnote 2

RKP can be split into the two following conditionals:

  • NEC: where one’s choice is p-dependent, if it is appropriate to treat p as a reason for acting, then S knows that p.

  • SUFF: where one’s choice is p-dependent, if S knows that p,  then it is appropriate to treat p as a reason for acting.

The claim that knowledge is the norm of practical reasoning has been followed by a wave of criticism. It has been remarked that data about our ordinary use of “know” only provides a very fragile basis for concluding that practical reasoning is governed by such a norm, since sometimes we use “knowing” in a loose sense, meaning “being certain” or “truly believing” (Gerken 2011, 2015; Littlejohn 2009). It has been argued that the same alleged data used to motivate the knowledge norm can be explained assuming other epistemic norms as well (Gerken 2011, 2015; Littlejohn 2009; Neta 2009). Moreover, in some cases the knowledge norm seems to fail to deliver the right verdict. For example, it seems that the knowledge norm cannot accommodate intuitions in Gettier-style cases in which the subject is blameless in treating a justified true belief that p as a reason for acting, even in the absence of knowledge (Brown 2008a, b; Gerken 2011; Littlejohn 2009).

Given these difficulties, some philosophers have opted for other weaker principles that not only are compatible with the original data motivating the knowledge norm, but also provide good explanations for the cases in which the knowledge norm delivers the wrong verdict. For instance, Littlejohn (2009, 2012) and Fantl and McGrath (2002) argue that the norm of practical reasoning is justified belief,Footnote 3 Gerken (2011) suggests that it is belief that p warranted to a degree that is adequate relative to the deliberative context, and Neta (2009) argues that it is justified belief that one knows that p. In spite of the divergence among these proposals, all of them hold that the norm of practical reasoning is belief plus some other property. Let’s call these epistemic norms of practical reasoning doxastic norms. As in the case of the knowledge norm, these norms can come in necessity and sufficiency versions depending on whether the relevant doxastic property is necessary or sufficient for appropriateness.

Against all these views, I doubt that there is an epistemic norm concerning the appropriateness conditions for treating a proposition as a reason for acting.Footnote 4 In this paper, I provide two counterexamples to the knowledge norm. I show cases in which it is appropriate for a subject to treat p as a reason for action even if the subject does not know that p. These are cases in which actions are grounded in acceptance and performed by a skeptic. These cases show that knowledge is not necessary for appropriately treating a proposition as a reason for action. Furthermore, I argue that, under a certain interpretation of epistemic norms, the first case constitutes a counterexample also to SUFF, according to which knowing that p is epistemically sufficient for appropriately treating p as a reason for acting. In addition, these cases are also good counterexamples against the alternative doxastic norms mentioned above including belief as a requisite, since in both counterexamples the subject does not even hold a belief about the relevant proposition. My final conclusion is that, even if knowledge, as well as justified belief, warranted belief, and similar doxastic attitudes, play an important role in the rationalization of many our actions, these attitudes are not necessary for appropriately treating a proposition as a reason for action. Moreover, according to a specific understanding of epistemic norms, they are even not sufficient. In many circumstances, different mental attitudes, such as acceptance, provide us with appropriate bases for action. Such cases show that there is no epistemic norm governing practical reasoning.Footnote 5

Before proceeding further, three clarifications are in order.Footnote 6 First, the upshot of my arguments is not that there is no norm at all governing practical reasoning. My arguments are consistent, for example, with the existence of other non-epistemic norms governing practical reasoning. The aim of my arguments is rather to provide counterexamples to the claim that practical reasoning is governed by an epistemic norm—a norm whose satisfaction condition is constituted by an epistemic notion such as (justified or warranted) belief or knowledge. This is precisely the crux of the debate on epistemic norms of practical reasoning introduced above.Footnote 7

Second, my examples aim to show that there are cases in practical reasoning in which it is appropriate to reason from premises that are not known or believed. This is compatible with the claim that other premises used in the same reasoning are known or believed. In all my examples below, the subject is rational in using premises she doesn’t know or believe in reasoning in which other premises are known. This is sufficient to show that there are no universally valid epistemic norms like RKP.Footnote 8

The third clarification concerns the specific sense in which these norms for practical reasoning count as epistemic. According to one obvious understanding, these norms are epistemic in virtue of the fact that they demand that some epistemic condition with respect to p be satisfied for it to be appropriate to use p as a premise in practical reasoning. According to another understanding, such norms are epistemic because they assess whether it is epistemically appropriate to use p as a premise in practical reasoning—where ‘epistemically’ characterizes the type of appropriateness and differentiates it from other types of appropriateness: prudential, rational, moral, aesthetic, etc.Footnote 9 While there is agreement on the fact that such norms are epistemic in the former sense, there is no consensus on whether they are also epistemic in the latter sense. Philosophers such as Fantl and McGrath (2009) and Gerken (2011) answer affirmatively to this question, whereas others, such as Brown (2008a, b), remain neutral on this issue, characterizing epistemic norms exclusively in the former sense. Still others, such as Hawthorne (2004) and Hawthorne and Stanley (2008), think that epistemic norms of practical reasoning are standards of rational appropriateness broadly conceived, not strictly epistemic. While my objections to NEC will be effective against both understandings of epistemic norms, my objection to SUFF will be specifically directed to views which do not conceive epistemic norms as standards of strictly epistemic appropriateness, such as the views of Hawthorne and Stanley.

2 Counterexamples to epistemic norms of practical reasoning

2.1 Acceptance and practical reasoning

For a long time philosophers of mind used to explain action within a belief-desire framework. According to this model, when we act we seek to realize our intentions and satisfy our desires in the light of what we believe. Similarly, in our practical reasoning we would reason from desires, beliefs and intentions to action. However, this philosophical orthodoxy has been called into question: some philosophers have argued that other attitudes can motivate action and figure as premises in practical reasoning. A mental attitude often discussed in the literature that plays an important role in our practical reasoning is acceptance. In what follows, I will illustrate the close tie between acceptance and practical reasoning and how it poses a serious challenge to the knowledge norm and other doxastic norms of practical reasoning.

Before discussing the relation between acceptance and practical reasoning, it is necessary to clarify the notion of acceptance relevant for the present discussion and how it differs from that of belief. According to some stipulative notions of acceptance, belief is a kind of acceptance. For example, David Velleman equates accepting that p with regarding p as true. Since believing necessarily involves regarding a proposition as true, it is a kind of acceptance. For Velleman, supposing, assuming, and propositional imagining are other kinds of acceptance (Velleman 2000, pp. 249–250). Similarly, for Crispin Wright, there is acceptance in all cases where the agent acts in a way as if she believes that proposition. Also according to this notion, belief is a type of acceptance. Other attitudes that fall into the category of acceptance include acting on the assumption that p, taking for granted that p and trusting that p for reasons that do not bear on considerations regarding the truth of p (Wright 2004, pp. 177–180).

On the contrary, according to a narrower and more natural reading of acceptance that I use here, acceptance and belief are two different kinds of mental attitude. Many have argued that acceptance in this narrower sense is an attitude widely adopted in our ordinary, religious, scientific and technological practices.Footnote 10 Here is an example adapted from Michael Bratman (1992, p. 5). I am in Rome on a June day and I am planning my journey to visit the city. I do not actually have a belief about whether it will rain or not, nor do I have sufficient reason to believe that it will not rain—e.g., the weather forecast for that day is not available and according to the records there have been some showers in June in past years. Nevertheless, in my present circumstances taking for granted that it will not rain simplifies my planning in a way that is useful. On the basis of that acceptance I decide to leave the umbrella at my hotel. Below I will consider other examples of acceptance.

It has been argued that acceptance differs from belief in at least three respects.Footnote 11 First, acceptance and belief differ from each other in terms of the requirements of rationality governing the two attitudes. Reasonable belief is peculiarly responsive to truth-conducive, epistemic factors; believing a proposition requires regarding it as true with the aim or commitment of getting its truth-value right.Footnote 12 On the contrary, acceptance doesn’t involve commitments to the truth of the accepted proposition.Footnote 13 There are no rational requirements to accept a proposition only if it is true. Accepting a proposition only involves treating it as if it were true, regardless of whether it is true or not.Footnote 14 This doesn’t mean that acceptances are not the object of rationality requirements and are not liable to criticisms. Standards for rational acceptance concern non-epistemic factors, such as instrumental, ethical and prudential considerations. Acceptances are assessed according to whether it is useful or convenient for the agent to accept p given her practical purposes, whether accepting p maximizes one’s expected utility, and so on.Footnote 15

Second, while belief is context independent or context invariant, acceptance is context dependent. When we believe something, we regard it as true no matter what our practical situation. By contrast, what one accepts can vary from context to context depending on the particular practical demands of the situation. These demands can sometimes make it reasonable for an agent to accept a proposition in a given context, even though she would not reasonably accept the same proposition in another context. While in planning my journey for a visit to Rome I reasonably accept that it will not rain, if I were figuring out what odds I would put in a bet on the weather I would not rely on that acceptance (Bratman 1992, p. 5). Contextual dependence of acceptance explains why, while belief is subject to an ideal of agglomeration across contexts—one should be able to or aim to integrate one’s various beliefs into one consistent and coherent larger view—one may accept certain things which do not cohere with her other beliefs, for mere practical reasons present in a specific context.

Third, acceptance and belief differ from each other with respect to voluntary control. Normally, believing a proposition is an involuntary mental state. It is a disposition I find myself having, a product of my automatic cognitive mechanism. Furthermore, one cannot form or revise a belief at will regardless of the evidence (or at least not in normal circumstances). By contrast, accepting a proposition is, or is generated by, a mental act involving voluntarily taking on a positive attitude toward a proposition depending on practical considerations.Footnote 16

By bearing this in mind, we can find a series of cases in which it is reasonable for the subject to accept that p under practical pressure, and appropriate to treat p as a reason for action, in spite of not having good reason to believe it (or even having good reasons to believe the contrary). All the situations in which it is rational to act on a proposition that is accepted but not believed constitute counterexamples to NEC and necessity versions of other doxastic norms.

A variant of Pascal’s Wager provides us with a good example here. Considerations about how it might be beneficial to live as if God exists cannot ground beliefs about God’s existence. Nonetheless, they are indeed good practical reasons for accepting that God exists.Footnote 17 Suppose one rationally decides to wager for the existence of God purely on the basis of a calculation of expected utility. This person would thereby accept but not believe that God exists. She would then take the proposition that God exists as a premise in her practical reasoning and simply endorse the policies and assent (at least externally) to the doctrines of the Church. She doesn’t need to make that calculation over and over again each time this proposition matters to her practical decisions; and she doesn’t even need to treat the believed proposition ‘if God exists and I don’t behave in accordance with God’s doctrines, then I will receive severe punishment after I die’ as a reason for action every time she engages in a relevant practical reasoning. Rather, in many circumstances she will simply treat the accepted proposition that God exists as a reason for her action. For example, she may be motivated by this acceptance to spend more time in the church and follow the precepts of religion.Footnote 18 Moreover, though she merely accepts that God exists, it seems that it is not inappropriate or irrational for her to treat that accepted proposition as a reason in her practical reasoning.

Another common situation in which it is appropriate to act on mere acceptance comes from scientific practices. There are cases in which the scientists’ actions are based on some background assumptions that they know to be false. For example, nobody in the scientific community believes in the validity and completeness of Newton’s theory of motion. But because of its convenience for making calculations in certain contexts, it is warranted for scientists to use Newton’s laws as premises in their reasoning, acting as if such laws were true, at least as long as the margins of error permit it. When used in practical reasoning, these laws can provide sufficiently precise predictions given specific practical purposes. This is compatible with scientists knowing that Newtonian laws are false.Footnote 19

The point can be generalized to the majority of natural laws. It is widely accepted in the scientific community that no contemporary physical theory is actually true. Science is far from having reached conclusive results. However, in practice scientists accept the available natural laws, using them as premises in at least some of their reasoning in order to calculate, design experiments and so on. Accepting natural laws in order to use them in one’s reasoning is very convenient in specific circumstances: it helps in achieving reasonably accurate conclusions in a simpler and faster way, even though the scientist is well aware that these laws are false.Footnote 20

A specific example could be useful here. A scientist, Mary, must deliberate about which specific act of computation she should perform in order to calculate the amount of fuel needed to get to the moon and back in a lunar module. Mary needs to calculate the amount of fuel quickly. She doesn’t have time to use General Relativity, which (let’s say) she actually knows to be the true theory. She can calculate the amount of fuel more quickly by using Newton’s laws, which Mary believes to be false but a good approximation to the truth for her present purposes. While Mary could well use as a premise in her reasoning something she knows— e.g., the complex proposition that [F=ma is the Newton’s law necessary for calculating the needed amount of fuel, and F=ma, though false, provides a good approximation given her present practical purposes]— we can well conceive circumstances in which Mary does not use this complex proposition as a premise in her reasoning, but rather reasons as follows:

  1. (1)

    I must calculate the vector sum of the force of O.

  2. (2)

    The vector sum of the force of an object is equal to the mass multiplied by its acceleration.

  3. (3)

    Therefore I shall multiply the mass of O by the acceleration of O.

The use of (2) in Mary’s reasoning instead of more complex propositions doesn’t look rationally impermissible. Reasoning directly from the accepted Newton’s law helps her in achieving the desired results in a faster and simpler way. It seems perfectly natural and reasonable to reason like this in similar circumstances. Indeed nobody would challenge reasoning (1)–(3) as inappropriate or rationally impermissible, and if Mary were asked why she drew conclusion (3), she could well cite in her defense the accepted proposition (2) instead of other known propositions.Footnote 21 This example seems to be a quite realistic representation of how many scientists engaging in practical reasoning use as premises in their reasoning some accepted proposition that they believe to be false when the desired results must not be overly precise.Footnote 22 \(^{,}\) Footnote 23

If one were not convinced by Mary’s case, here is another more familiar example from our philosophical practice. When we calculate the subjective probability of some propositions by updating evidence using Bayesian conditionalization, we know (or at least believe) that there are more precise rules for updating evidence (e.g., Jeffrey conditionalization), and thus that the proposition expressing Bayesian conditionalization is literally false. Nevertheless if we are in contexts in which we are not concerned with a high level of accuracy (for example, if we are trying to solve basic exercises in a Decision Theory course), we make as if the proposition expressing Bayesian conditionalization were true. When we reason from this proposition in such contexts, we deliberately overlook the fact that it is inaccurate and we move automatically to a conclusion, as we would do in reasoning from a belief. This way of reasoning from accepted propositions that we believe to be false (or at least we would hardly say we believe) in our philosophical practice seems to me both common and perfectly rational.

In both the exemplified cases of the Pascalian wager and the scientific practice, it seems perfectly rational for an agent to treat a proposition that is accepted but not believed as a reason for action. These cases constitute counterexamples to NEC and necessity versions of other doxastic norms.

From the case of scientific practice, we can also develop a counterexample to certain versions of SUFF. As I said in Sect. 1, while some philosophers interpret epistemic norms as concerning a specifically epistemic sense of appropriateness, others conceive appropriateness in a more liberal sense (for example as substantive rational permissibility). The example I will consider below is problematic for all those endorsing the latter interpretation of SUFF (e.g. Hawthorne and Stanley 2008). A counterexample to this version of SUFF is one in which S knows that p,  but given the setting of S’s situation, it is not rationally permissible for S to treat p as a reason for acting. Consider again the above scenario in which Mary knows the true and complex physical law of General Relativity necessary to calculate the precise amount of fuel needed for a lunar module to get to the moon and back. We can imagine a similar situation in which it is not rationally permissible for her to take that known proposition as a premise in her reasoning. Suppose again that Mary needs to calculate the amount of fuel only to a rough approximation, but it is particularly urgent that she does that in a very short time (e.g., she has only twenty seconds to enter an estimation of the amount of fuel into the control system of a machine).Footnote 24 In such a situation, since adopting Newtonian laws would perfectly suffice for the purpose, it would be unreasonable for her to use the complex law in her calculations. This is incompatible with SUFF. Note that Mary’s epistemic position with respect to the proposition expressing the true physical law is also strong enough to satisfy the constraints required by other epistemic norms (justified belief that p, warranted belief that p to a degree that is adequate relative to deliberative context, or justified belief that S knows that p). And in the described situation it is inappropriate for her to use that proposition as a premise in her practical reasoning no matter how strong her epistemic position is with respect to that proposition. Therefore, all the sufficiency versions of other epistemic norms, if interpreted in the liberal sense considered above, are confronted with a problem in dealing with this type of case as well.Footnote 25

A possible worry here could be that since acceptance doesn’t involve rational commitments to the truth of the accepted proposition, acceptances are not liable to rational criticism and thus cannot serve as rationalizers of an action or a deliberation when used as premises in practical reasoning.Footnote 26 However, I think that this worry is misplaced. As I said above, acceptances can be rationally assessed and criticized according to practical standards, and agents using acceptances as premises in practical reasoning are liable to rational criticism according to these standards. For example, if one concludes that accepting that God exists has the best expected utility, but then accepts that God doesn’t exist and uses this acceptance as a premise in her reasoning, her acceptance can be assessed as unwarranted, and premising this proposition in her reasoning is liable to criticism. Similarly, consider the case of an engineer who accepts some law of Newton’s theory in a context in which this theory doesn’t provide sufficiently precise predictions for her specific practical purposes (e.g., for designing a particle collider machine), and she applies such laws as premises in her reasoning in that context (e.g., for making calculations whose results are necessary to design hadron accelerators). The reasoning of this engineer is liable to criticism and her acceptance cannot rationalize her action. This is because that acceptance is unreasonable given the practical purposes of the engineer in that context.

2.2 Rational action performed by the skeptic

Consider the following dialogue in which a skeptic (K) is trying to convince her friend (F) that she doesn’t know that there is an external world.

  • K: “Do you know that you are not a brain in a vat?”

  • F: “No, I don’t know.”

  • K: “If you are a brain in a vat, then you cannot hold this cup of coffee in your hand, because you don’t have hands at all. So, since you don’t know that you are not a brain in a vat, you don’t know that you have a cup of coffee in your hand.”

    After brief thought, F concludes: “Yes, you are right, I don’t know that.” Thus she suspends her judgment. At the same time, F moves her cup to her lips and drinks the coffee.

I assume that: (1) F takes the conversation seriously and answers K sincerely, i.e., F does not give that answer to K due to any non-epistemic considerations, such as social graces and reluctance to displease her friend; rather, F is truly convinced by K’s reasoning and suspends her judgment as a consequence of that reasoning; (2) in moving the cup F genuinely exercises her agency; (3) the proposition that there is a cup of coffee in F’s hand (hereafter, H) is one of the reasons motivating her action; (4) The proposition that F treats as a reason for lifting her hand is H, not some complex proposition such as that, whether or not she is a BIV, seemingly lifting her hand will cause a pleasant taste and sensation of warmth.

Now, intuitively, it seems that F’s action cannot be criticized as irrational.Footnote 27 According to NEC, if it is appropriate for F to treat H as a reason for acting, then F knows H. But F voluntarily suspended her belief that H. F doesn’t believe H anymore, and consequently does not know that H. This is a counterexample to NEC.

It might be argued that in the above example there are other beliefs (plausibly amounting to knowledge) which F may be using as premises in her practical reasoning—in particular the belief that there might be a cup of coffee in front of F. Given the low cost of the action, this belief seems sufficient to rationalize it.Footnote 28 This objection can be addressed by considering other analogous cases in which the skeptic doesn’t merely suspend her judgment on the relevant proposition but believes that proposition to be false. Consider domain-relative forms of skepticism, such as skepticism about the existence of objects in the domains of mathematics, modality, ethics, etc. Such forms of skepticism are compatible with fictionalism with respect to each of these domains. For example, a fictionalist skeptic about mathematics holds that we should not believe in the existence of mathematical objects and we should regard sentences about mathematical objects, not as aiming at literal truth, but as telling part of a fictional story. For this skeptic, even if mathematical sentences are all false, engaging in a discourse about mathematics is rational because of its utility (Leng 2015). Similarly, the fictionalist can rationally act as if those sentences were true. Lacking beliefs about mathematical propositions doesn’t make the use of these propositions as premises in one’s reasoning irrational or unreasonable. A fictionalist mathematician can perfectly well use sentences such as ‘7 + 5 = 12’ or ‘There are no square prime numbers’ as premises in her reasoning (both theoretical and practical); she can continue doing mathematics by adopting non-doxastic attitudes towards ordinary mathematical propositions.Footnote 29 In such cases, a skeptic about a certain area of discourse overtly believes that a proposition is false (and thus that it might not be true), but relies on it in her reasoning as if it were true. One can see the skeptic about the external world in my previous example as relying on an analogous sort of attitude in her practical reasoning.

One may object that F still involuntarily believes that H even though she would not be voluntarily willing to assent to it (Pritchard 2000, p. 203). If this were the case, according to some externalist account of knowledge, F would know that H as long as some external condition is satisfied—for instance, if F’s belief that H were reliably formed. Furthermore, Williamson (2000) convincingly argues that knowledge is not a luminous mental state: one is not always in a position to reflectively know that she knows something. In the light of the above observations, one could say that what F lacks in the scenario is the higher-order knowledge that she knows that p, but not the first-order knowledge that p.

A possible way to defend the step from F’s claimed suspension of judgment about H to F’s ignorance of that proposition is by assuming that, even if in general knowledge may not be transparent to a subject, there are possible situations in which a subject in a case like that of F has an appropriate access to her own epistemic states. The possible failure of transparency in some cases does not entail that one is always wrong about her first-order mental states. In particular, it is possible to conceive a scenario like the one described above such that, when F sincerely asserts that she doesn’t know that H, she has a full epistemic access to the fact that she withholds her belief that H. In such a possible case, F would thereby not know that H. Even one single possible case like this is sufficient to provide a counterexample to NEC.Footnote 30

A more powerful objection is the following. There are possible ways of interpreting what’s going on in F’s psychology in the above case, some of which is incompatible with the case being a counterexample to NEC. For example, Egan (2008) has recently argued for the view that the systems of belief that we in fact have are fragmented and could include subsets of beliefs which are possibly inconsistent. This view is opposed to idealized models of human cognition according to which our beliefs would be part of a single coherent system. In the above case, one can interpret F’s cognitive system as fragmented, her skepticism not affecting her belief that H. If so, F can rely on the belief that H in her action. So described, the case wouldn’t constitute a counterexample to NEC.Footnote 31

I concede that it’s a much debated question in philosophy of psychology how to interpret similar cases, and that a “fragmented mind” hypothesis seems a possible way of interpreting what’s going on in F’s psychology in the above example. I admit that there are several possible interpretations of the case, some of which incompatible with the case being a counterexample to NEC. But remember here that in order to make my point, all that I need is that there be at least one psychologically possible description of the example (or similar examples) under which F doesn’t believe that H. The possibility of a single case in which F doesn’t believe that H would be already a counterexample to NEC. This is perfectly compatible with there being other descriptions of this and similar cases according to which the subject believes the relevant proposition (as in the “fragmented mind” interpretation). However, in the present context I cannot settle the issue of whether a description of the case that suits my purposes is psychologically possible. For this reason, I will set this issue aside and for the sake of argument I will simply assume that a similar description is indeed possible. My conclusion about the present case will thus be merely conditional: assuming an interpretation of this (or some similar) case as one in which the subject doesn’t believe the target proposition, the case constitutes a counterexample to NEC.Footnote 32

2.3 A reply to a possible objection

One could defend the knowledge norm by arguing that though the agent in those cases seems to be blameless, he/she does violate the knowledge norm. Hawthorne and Stanley consider a situation in which someone in a situation of urgency is intuitively blameless in acting on mere partial belief. They claim that this kind of case doesn’t ultimately threaten the knowledge norm; according to them, “the fact that we do not blame someone forced into a quick decision is no evidence at all against it” (Hawthorne and Stanley 2008, p. 587). In their view, the agent is blameless because the practical circumstances excuse her for violating the knowledge norm. Similarly, Hawthorne and Stanley could object to the above counterexamples by saying that the agent violates the norm but is excusable, for in these situations practical considerations render it excusable to act on less than knowledge.

Here are two replies. First, in the exemplified cases it is hard to see in what sense the agent needs to be excused. Our intuition suggests that the agent does not violate any epistemic constraint on practical rationality. For instance, when scientists have good reasons to use an out-of-date Newtonian law as a premise in their calculation, we neither judge them as acting inappropriately in any sense nor do we feel them in need of excuse for some wrongdoing. In these cases, there is no indication of the violation of some normative standard, either practical or epistemic: no criticizability, no blameability or excusability according to any normative assessment whatsoever.

Second, the maneuver of appealing to excuses is rather unpromising. Gerken (2011) points out that unless upholders of the knowledge norm can specify the notions of excuse and/or blamelessness, an appeal to excuses would be ad hoc and thus unconvincing. He then critically considers several possible principled accounts of excuse, and argues that none of them is free from serious problems. It seems even more implausible to work out a viable account of excuse able to accommodate the types of cases considered above, not to mention that each of them involves completely different sorts of circumstances.Footnote 33

3 Conclusion

What conditions make it appropriate to treat p as a reason for action? In this paper, I argued that neither knowing that p nor believing that p are necessary or sufficient conditions for appropriately treating p as a reason for action. Notice however that the aim of this paper was not to criticize RKP and other doxastic norms of practical reasoning on the ground that knowledge or warranted belief don’t play any role for the rationalization of actions. Rather, it was to point out the limits of these principles by showing how rational actions may be based in some cases on other mental attitude such as acceptance.