Synthese

, Volume 193, Issue 10, pp 3383–3395 | Cite as

Competing accounts of contrastive coherence

Article

Abstract

The proposition that Tweety is a bird coheres better with the proposition that Tweety has wings than with the proposition that Tweety cannot fly. This relationship of contrastive coherence is the focus of the present paper. Based on recent work in formal epistemology we consider various possibilities to model this relationship by means of probability theory. In a second step we consider different applications of these models. Among others, we offer a coherentist interpretation of the conjunction fallacy.

Keywords

Contrastivism Coherence Probability Confirmation  Bayesian epistemology Conjunction fallacy 

References

  1. Blauw, M. (Ed.). (2013). Contrastivism in philosophy. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
  2. BonJour, L. (1985). The structure of empirical knowledge. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  3. Bovens, L., & Hartmann, S. (2003). Bayesian epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  4. Bovens, L., & Olsson, E. J. (2000). Coherentism, reliability and Bayesian networks. Mind, 109, 685–719.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Brössel, P. (2013). The problem of measure sensitivity redux. Philosophy of Science, 80, 378–397.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Chandler, J. (2007). Solving the tacking problem with contrast classes. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 58, 489–502.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Chandler, J. (2013). Contrastive confirmation: Some competing accounts. Synthese, 190, 129–138.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Chart, D. (2001). Inference to the best explanation, Bayesianism, and feminist bank tellers. Online-paper. http://philsci-archice.pitt.edu/documents/disk0/00/00/03/22/.
  9. Crupi, V., Festa, R., & Buttasi, C. (2010). Towards a grammar of Bayesian confirmation. In M. Surez, M. Dorato, & M. Rdei (Eds.), Epistemology and methodology of science (pp. 73–93). Berlin: Springer.Google Scholar
  10. Crupi, V., Fitelson, B., & Tentori, K. (2008). Probability, confirmation, and the conjunction fallacy. Thinking and Reasoning, 14, 182–199.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Crupi, V., & Tentori, K. (2012). A second look at the logic of explanatory power (with two new representation theorems). Philosophy of Science, 79, 365–385.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Crupi, V., Tentori, K., & Gonzalez, M. (2007). On Bayesian measures of evidential support: Theoretical and empirical issues. Philosophy of Science, 74, 229–252.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. de Finetti, B. ([1937] 1980). Foresight: Its logical laws, its subjective sources. In H. E. Kyburg, Jr. & H. E. Smokler (Eds.), Studies in subjective probability (2nd ed., pp. 53–118). Huntington, NY: Robert E. Krieger.Google Scholar
  14. Douven, I., & Meijs, W. (2007). Measuring coherence. Synthese, 156, 405–425.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Eells, E., & Fitelson, B. (2000). Measuring confirmation and evidence. Journal of Philosophy, 97, 663–672.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Fitelson, B. (1999). The plurality of Bayesian measures of confirmation and the problem of measure sensitivity. Philosophy of Science, 66, 362–378.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Fitelson, B. (2003). A probabilistic theory of coherence. Analysis, 63, 194–199.Google Scholar
  18. Fitelson, B. (2007). Likelihoodism, Bayesianism, and relational confirmation. Synthese, 156, 473–489.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Fitelson, B. (2008). A decision procedure for probability calculus with applications. The Review of Symbolic Logic, 1, 111–125.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Gigerenzer, G. (1994). Why the distinction between single-event probabilities and frequencies is important for psychology (and vice versa). In G. Wright & P. Ayton (Eds.), Subjective probability (pp. 129–161). New York: Wiley.Google Scholar
  21. Gigerenzer, G. (1996). On narrow norms and vague heuristics: A rebuttal to Kahneman and Tversky. Psychological Review, 103, 592–596.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Gigerenzer, G. (2001). Content-blind norms, no norms, or good norms? A reply to Vranas. Cognition, 81, 93–103.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Glass, D. H. (2002). Coherence, explanation, and Bayesian networks. In M. ONeill, et al. (Eds.), Artificial intelligence and cognitive science (pp. 177–182). Berlin: Springer.Google Scholar
  24. Glass, D. H. (2007). Coherence measures and inference to the best explanation. Synthese, 157, 275–296.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Good, I. J. (1960). Weight of evidence, corroboration, explanatory power, information and the utility of experiments. Journal of the Royal Statistical Society (Series B), 22, 319–331.Google Scholar
  26. Grice, H. P. (1975). Logic and conversation. Studies in the way of words (pp. 22–40). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  27. Hertwig, R., & Chase, V. M. (1998). Many reasons or just one: How response mode affects reasoning in the conjunction problem. Thinking and Reasoning, 4, 319–352.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Hertwig, R., & Gigerenzer, G. (1999). The ‘conjunction fallacy’ revisited: How intelligent inferences look like reasoning errors. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 12, 275–305.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Hitchcock, C. R. (1996). The role of contrast in causal and explanatory claims. Synthese, 107, 395–419.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Hitchcock, C. D. (1999). Contrastive explanation and the demons of determinism. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 50, 585–612.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Joyce, J. (2004). Bayes’s theorem. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.). The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Summer 2004 ed.). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2004/entries/bayes-theorem/.
  32. Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1972). Subjective probability: A judgment of representativeness. In D. Kahneman, P. Slovic, & A. Tversky (Eds.), Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristics and biases. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  33. Kemeny, J., & Oppenheim, P. (1952). Degrees of factual support. Philosophy of Science, 19, 307–324.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Lipton, P. (1990). Contrastive explanation. In D. Knowles (Ed.), Explanation and its limits (pp. 247–266). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  35. McGrew, T. (2003). Confirmation, heuristics, and explanatory reasoning. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 54, 553–567.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Mellers, A., Hertwig, R., & Kahneman, D. (2001). Do frequency representations eliminate conjunction effects? An exercise in adversarial collaboration. Psychological Science, 12, 269–275.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Olsson, E. J. (2002). What is the problem of coherence and truth? The Journal of Philosophy, 99, 246–272.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Ramsey, F. P. (1926). Truth and probability. In H. E. Kyburg Jr & H. E. Smokler (Eds.), Studies in subjective probability (2nd ed., pp. 23–52). Huntington, NY: R. E. Krieger. 1980.Google Scholar
  39. Reichenbach, H. (1949). The theory of probability. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
  40. Roche, W., & Schippers, M. (2013). Coherence, probability and explanation. Erkenntnis, 79, 821–828.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Royal, R. (1997). Statistical evidence: A likelihood paradigm. London: Chapman and Hall.Google Scholar
  42. Schippers, M. (2014). Probabilistic measures of coherence. From adequacy constraints towards pluralism. Synthese, 191, 3821–3845.Google Scholar
  43. Schippers, M. (2015). The grammar of Bayesian coherentism. Studia Logica, 103, 955–984.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. Schupbach, J. N., & Sprenger, J. (2011). The logic of explanatory power. Philosophy of Science, 78, 105–127.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. Shafir, E., Smith, E., & Osherson, D. (1990). Typicality and reasoning fallacies. Memory and Cognition, 18, 229–239.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. Shogenji, T. (1999). Is coherence truth conducive? Analysis, 59, 338–345.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. Shogenji, T. (2012). The degree of epistemic justification and the conjunction fallacy. Synthese, 184, 29–48.Google Scholar
  48. Sides, A., Osherson, D., Bonini, N., & Viale, R. (2002). On the reality of the conjunction fallacy. Memory and Cognition, 30, 191–198.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  49. Siebel, M. (2003). There’s something about Linda: Probability, coherence and rationality. Unpublished manuscript.Google Scholar
  50. Siebel, M. (2005). Against probabilistic measures of coherence. Erkenntnis, 63, 335–360.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  51. Siebel, M. (2011). Why explanation and thus coherence cannot be reduced to probability. Analysis, 71, 264–266.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  52. Tentori, K., & Crupi, V. (2012). On the conjunction fallacy and the meaning of and yet again: A reply to Hertwig, Benz, and Krauss (2008). Cognition, 122, 123–134.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  53. Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1982). Judgments of and by representativeness. In D. Kahneman, P. Slovic, & A. Tversky (Eds.), Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristics and biases (pp. 84–98). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  54. von Mises, R. (1957). Probability, statistics and truth. New York: Macmillan.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2015

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.University of OldenburgOldenburgGermany

Personalised recommendations