Worlds, times and selves revisited
- 162 Downloads
Abstract
In Prior’s tense-logical analysis, we can avoid mentioning instants in our language by construing them as propositions of a special kind. Instead of qualifying instants by predicates, we may qualify propositions by modalities. Prior shows that by changing the informal interpretation of our modal-like language, we can similarly attempt to avoid ontological commitments to worlds (modal logic) and even to selves and other bona fide individuals (egocentric logic). As he notes, the paraphrasing strategy works too generally to be of direct metaphysical use. I wish to speak of several types of entities within one and the same language. This leads to the issue of cross-context identity: how to make sense of speaking of the same entity of one type relative to distinct entities of another type. My analysis employs the notion of world line. I discern a structure of mutually interrelated categories with three informal interpretations: tense, modal and egocentric. They correspond to different metaphysical views on the interrelations of time, logical alternatives and individuals. Prior’s dilemma regarding the possibility of modalizing, not only our talk concerning times and worlds, but even our discourse pertaining to the ‘real world of individuals’ does not vanish but reappears also in my setting.
Keywords
Cross-context identity Egocentric logic Modality TimeNotes
Acknowledgments
I am indebted to the anonymous referees for their useful remarks. An earlier version of this paper was presented in the Arthur Prior Centenary Conference at Balliol College, Oxford; I am grateful for the comments received from participants.
References
- Alexander, H. G. (Ed.). (1956). The Leibniz–Clarke correspondence. Manchester: Manchester University Press.Google Scholar
- Belnap, N., & Müller, T. (2014). CIFOL: Case-intensional first order logic. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 43(2–3), 393–437.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Blackburn, P. (2006). Arthur Prior and hybrid logic. Synthese, 150(3), 329–372.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Bressan, A. (1972). A general interpreted modal calculus. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
- Hawley, K. (2001). How things persist. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
- Hintikka, J. (1969). Models for modalities. Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar
- Hintikka, J. (1975). The intentions of intentionality. Dordrecht: Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Kracht, M., & Kutz, O. (2007). Logically possible worlds and counterpart semantics for modal logic. In D. Jacquette (Ed.), Philosophy of logic (pp. 943–995). Amsterdam: Elsevier.Google Scholar
- Leibniz, G. W. (1954 [1714]). In: A. Robinet (Ed.), Principes de la Nature et de la grâce fondées en raison et Principes de la philosophie ou Monadologie. Paris: Presses Universitaires de FranceGoogle Scholar
- Lewis, D. (1986). Philosophical papers (Vol. 2). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
- Prior, A. (1967). Past, present and future. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Prior, A. (1968). Papers on time and tense. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
- Prior, A., & Fine, K. (1977). Worlds, times and selves. London: Duckworth.Google Scholar
- Putnam, H. (1977). Realism and reason. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 50(6), 483–498.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Schurz, G. (1997). The is-ought problem. Dordrecht: Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Tulenheimo, T. (2009). Remarks on individuals in modal contexts. Revue Internationale de Philosophie, 63(250), 383–394.Google Scholar
- Tulenheimo, T. (2015). Cross-world identity, temporal quantifiers and the question of tensed contents. In A. Torza (Ed.), Quantifiers, quantifiers, and quantifiers (pp. 409–461). New York: Springer.Google Scholar