Advertisement

Synthese

, Volume 194, Issue 1, pp 67–78 | Cite as

Carnap and the invariance of logical truth

  • Steve AwodeyEmail author
S.I. : Carnap on Logic

Abstract

The failed criterion of logical truth proposed by Carnap in the Logical Syntax of Language was based on the determinateness of all logical and mathematical statements. It is related to a conception which is independent of the specifics of the system of the Syntax, hints of which occur elsewhere in Carnap’s writings, and those of others. What is essential is the idea that the logical terms are invariant under reinterpretation of the empirical terms, and are therefore semantically determinate. A certain objection to Carnap’s version of the invariance conception has been repeated several times in the literature. It is based on Gödel incompleteness, which is puzzling, since Carnap’s Syntax is otherwise quite careful to take account of Gödel. We show here that, in fact, the objection is invalid and is based on a confusion about determinacy. Sorting this out is worthwhile not only for the purpose of better understanding Carnap’s thinking in the Syntax, though. The invariance conception is also related to recent work in the philosophy of logic regarding “logicality”—the characterization of logical concepts—following a proposal of Tarski’s. It is even connected to some very recent developments in the foundations of mathematics.

Keywords

Carnap Invariance Analyticity Logical syntax Logicality Univalence 

Notes

Acknowledgments

Thanks to Hannes Leitgeb for inviting me to the Munich Center for Mathematical Philosophy where this work was done, to Georg Schiemer for organizing the workshop where it was presented, and to André Carus for much valuable input on the ideas contained herein and crucial assistance in actually writing the paper.

References

  1. Awodey, S. (2012). “Explicating ‘analytic’ ”. In P. Wagner (Ed.), Carnap’s ideal of explication and naturalism. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
  2. Awodey, S. (2012). Type theory and homotopy. In P. Dybjer, et al. (Eds.), Epistemology versus ontology: Essays in honor of Per Martin-Löf (Vol. 27, pp. 183–201)., Logic, epistemology, and the unity of science Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Awodey, S., & Carus, A. W. (2001). Carnap, completeness, and categoricity: The Gabelbarkeitssatz of 1928. Erkenntnis, 54, 145–172.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Awodey, S., & Carus, A. W. (2009). From Wittgenstein’s prison to the boundless ocean: Carnap’s dream of logical syntax. In P. Wagner (Ed.), Carnap’s logical syntax of language. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
  5. Awodey, S., & Carus, A. W. (2010). Gödel and Carnap. In S. Feferman, C. Parsons, & S. Simpson (Eds.), Kurt G \(\ddot{d}\) el: Essays for his centennial. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  6. Awodey, S., & Forssell, H. (2013). First-order logical duality. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 164(3), 319–348.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Beth, E. W. (1963). Carnap’s views on the advantages of constructed systems over natural languages in the philosophy of science. In P. Schilpp (Ed.), The philosophy of Rudolf Carnap (pp. 469–502). Chicago: Open Court.Google Scholar
  8. Bonnay, D. (2008). Logicality and invariance. Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, 14(1), 29–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Carnap, R. (1927). Eigentliche und uneigentliche Begriffe. Symposion, 1, 355–374.Google Scholar
  10. Carnap, R. Beweis der Unmöglichkeit einer Gabelung der Arithmetik. Unpublished note dated 12.6.27. Young Research Library, UCLA, Manuscript collection #1029, Rudolf Carnap Papers, Box 1, folder 1.Google Scholar
  11. Carnap, R. (1934). Logische Syntax der Sprache. Vienna: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Carnap, R. (1942). Introduction to semantics. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  13. Carnap, R. (1947). Meaning and necessity. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  14. Carnap, R. (1950). Logical foundations of probability. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  15. Feferman, S. (2010). Set-theoretical invariance criteria for logicality. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 51(1), 3–20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Friedman, M. (1999). Tolerance and analyticity in Carnaps philosophy of mathematics. In M. Friedman (Ed.), Reconsidering logical positivism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Friedman, M., & Creath, R. (Eds.). (2007). Carnap’s quest for analyticity. Cambridge compainion to Carnap. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  18. Frost-Arnold, G. (2013). Carnap, Tarski, and Quine at Harvard: Conversations on logic, mathematics and science. Chicago: Open Court.Google Scholar
  19. Goldfarb, W., & Ricketts, T. (1992). Carnap and the philosophy of mathematics. In D. Bell & W. Vossenkuhl (Eds.), Science and subjectivity: The Vienna circle and twentieth-century philosophy (pp. 61–78). Berlin: Akademie-Verlag.Google Scholar
  20. Mac Lane, S. (1938). Carnap on logical syntax. Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society, 44, 171–176.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Sher, G. (1991). The bounds of logic: A generalized viewpoint. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  22. Tarski, A. (1986). What are logical notions? In J. Corcoran (Ed.), History and philosophy of logic (Vol. 7, pp. 143–154). Amsterdam: Elsevier.Google Scholar
  23. Tarski, A., & Lindenbaum, A. (1956). On the limitations of deductive theories, 1936. In Logic, semantics, metamathematics: Papers from 1923 to 1938 by Alfred Tarski (J. H. Woodger, Ed., Trans.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  24. The Univalent Foundations Program. (2013). Homotopy type theory: Univalent foundations of mathematics. Princeton: Institute for Advanced Study.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2015

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Carnegie Mellon UniversityPittsburghUSA

Personalised recommendations