Advertisement

Synthese

, Volume 192, Issue 9, pp 2955–2986 | Cite as

Active externalism, virtue reliabilism and scientific knowledge

  • Spyridon Orestis Palermos
Article

Abstract

Combining active externalism in the form of the extended and distributed cognition hypotheses with virtue reliabilism can provide the long sought after link between mainstream epistemology and philosophy of science. Specifically, by reading virtue reliabilism along the lines suggested by the hypothesis of extended cognition, we can account for scientific knowledge produced on the basis of both hardware and software scientific artifacts (i.e., scientific instruments and theories). Additionally, by bringing the distributed cognition hypothesis within the picture, we can introduce the notion of epistemic group agents, in order to further account for collective knowledge produced on the basis of scientific research teams.

Keywords

Active externalism Virtue reliabilism Hypothesis of extended cognition Scientific knowledge Epistemic group agents Hypothesis of distributed cognition 

Notes

Acknowledgments

I am grateful to J. Adam Carter and John Greco for very useful discussions on the topic and feedback on previous drafts. I am also thankful to two anonymous referees for Synthese for their particularly insightful reviews. Research into the area of this paper was supported by the AHRC-funded ‘Extended Knowledge’ Project, based at the Eidyn research centre, University of Edinburgh.

References

  1. Adams, F., & Aizawa, K. (2001). The bounds of cognition. Philosophical Psychology, 14(1), 43–64. doi: 10.1080/09515080120033571.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Adams, F., & Aizawa, K. (2010). The bounds of cognition (1st ed.). Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Bach-y-Rita, P., & Kercel, S. W. (2003). Sensory substitution and the human-machine interface. Trends in Cognitive Science, 7(12), 541–6.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Baehr, J. (2006). Character, reliability and virtue epistemology. The Philosophical Quarterly, 56(223), 193–212. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-9213.2006.00437.x.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Bamberger, J. S., & Brofsky, H. (1979). The art of listening: Developing musical perception. New York: Harper & Row.Google Scholar
  6. Barnes, B., Bloor, D., & Henry, J. (1996). Scientific knowledge: A sociological analysis. Edinburgh: A&C Black.Google Scholar
  7. Barnier, A. J., Sutton, J., Harris, C. B., & Wilson, R. A. (2008). A conceptual and empirical framework for the social distribution of cognition: The case of memory. Cognitive Systems Research, 9(1–2), 33–51.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Berk, L., & Garvin, R. (1984). Development of private speech among low-income appalachian children. Developmental Psychology, 20(2), 271–286.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Block, N. (2002). Concepts of consciousness. In D. Chalmers (Ed.), Philosophy of mind: Classical and contemporary readings (pp. 206–219). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  10. Bloomfield, L. (1933). Language. New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston.Google Scholar
  11. Bloor, D. (1991). Knowledge and social imagery. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  12. Braddon-Mitchell, D., & Jackson, F. (2006). Philosophy of mind and cognition: An introduction (2nd ed.). Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
  13. Brewer, F.W. & Lambert, B.L. (2001). The theory ladeness of observation and the theory-ladeness of the rest of the scientific process. Philosophy of Science, Vol. 68, No. 3, Supplement: Proceedings of the 2000 Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association. Part I: Contributed Papers, (pp. S176–S186).Google Scholar
  14. Burge, T. (1986). Individualism and psychology. Philosophical Review, 95, 3–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Carter, J. A., Kallestrup, J., Palermos, S. O., & Pritchard, D. (2014). Varieties of externalism. Philosophical Issues, 24(1), 63–109.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Chalmers, D. (1996). The conscious mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  17. Chemero, A. (2009). Radical embodied cognitive science. Cambridge: MIT press.Google Scholar
  18. Chemla, P. K. (2012). The history of mathematical proof in ancient traditions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  19. Churchland, P. M. (1979). Scientific realism and the plasticity of the mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Churchland, P. M. (1988). Perceptual plasticity and theoretical neutrality: A reply to Jerry Fodor. Philosophy of Science, 55, 167–187.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Churchland, P. M. (1989). A neurocomputational perspective. The nature of mind and the structure of science. Cambridge: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
  22. Clark, A. (1998). Magic words, how language augments human computation. In P. Carruthers & J. Boucher (Eds.), Language and thought: Interdisciplinary themes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  23. Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended mind. Ananlysis, 58(1), 7–19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Clark, A. (2007). Curing cognitive hiccups: A defense of the extended mind. The Journal of Philosophy, 104, 163–192.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Clark, A. (2008). Supersizing the mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Estany, A. (2001). The thesis of theory-laden observation in the light of cognitive psychology. Philosophy of Science, 68(2), 203–217.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Feyerabend, P. K. (1975). Against method: Outline of an anarchistic theory of knowledge. New York: New Left Books.Google Scholar
  28. Fodor, J. (1984). Observation reconsidered. Philosophy of Science, 51, 23–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Fodor, J. (1988). A reply to Churchland’s ‘perceptual plasticity and theoretical neutrality. Philosophy of Science, 55, 188–198.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Froese, T., Gershenson, C., & Rosenblueth, D.A. (2013). The dynamically extended mind. Retrieved http://arxiv.org/abs/1305.1958.
  31. Fuller, S. (2007). The knowledge book: Key concepts in philosophy, science and culture. Durham: Acumen.Google Scholar
  32. Fuller, S. (2012). Social epistemology: A quarter-century itinerary. Social Epistemology, 26(3–4), 267–83.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Giere, R. (1988). Explaining science: A cognitive approach. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Giere, R. (2002a). Discussion note: Distributed cognition in epistemic cultures. Philosophy of Science, 69, 637–644.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Giere, R. (2002b). Scientific cognition as distributed cognition. In Peter Carruthers, Stephen Stitch, & Michael Siegal (Eds.), Cognitive bases of science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  36. Giere, R., & Moffat, B. (2003). Distributed cognition: Where the cognitive and the social merge. Social Studies of Science, 33/2, 1–10.Google Scholar
  37. Giere, R. (2006). The role of agency in distributed cognitive systems. Philosophy of Science, 73, 710–719.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Giere, R. (2007). Distributed cognition without distributed knowing. Social Epistemology, 21(3), 313–320.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Gilbert, M. (2007c). Remarks on collective belief. Socializing Epistemology: The Social Dimensions of Knowledge 1994. Retrieved at SSRN: http://ssrn.com/abstract=1052361.
  40. Gilbert, M. (2007a). Collective epistemology. Episteme, 1(2), 95–107. doi: 10.3366/epi.2004.1.2.95.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Gilbert, M. (2007b). Modeling collective belief. Synthese, 73, 185–204.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Gilbert, M. (2010). Belief and acceptance as features of groups. Protosociology: An International Journal of Interdisciplinary Research, 16, 35–69.Google Scholar
  43. Goldman, A. (2004). Group knowledge versus group rationality: Two approaches to social epistemology. Episteme, 1(01), 11–22.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. Goldman, A. (2010). Why social epistemology is real epistemology. In Adrian Haddock, Alan Millar, & Duncan Pritchard (Eds.), Social epistemology (pp. 1–28). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. Goody, J. (1977). The domestication of the savage mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  46. Goody, J. (1986). The logic of writing and the organization of society. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. Goody, J. (1987). The interface between the oral and the written. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  48. Greco, J. (1999). Agent reliabilism. In James Tomberlin (Ed.), Philosophical perspectives 13: Epistemology (pp. 273–296). Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview Press.Google Scholar
  49. Greco, J., & Zagzebski, L. (2000). Two kinds of intellectual virtue. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 60(1), 179. doi: 10.2307/2653438.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  50. Greco, J. (2004). Knowledge as credit for true belief. In M. DePaul & L. Zagzebski (Eds.), Intellectual virtue: Perspectives from ethics and epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  51. Greco, J. (2007). The nature of ability and the purpose of knowledge. Philosophical Issues, 17, 57–69.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  52. Greco, J. (2010). Achieving knowledge: A virtue-theoretic account of epistemic normativity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  53. Hanson, N. R. (1961). Patterns of discovery. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  54. Hanson, N. R. (1969). Perception and discovery; An introduction to scientific inquiry. San Francisco: Freeman, Cooper.Google Scholar
  55. Harris, R. (1989). How does writing restructure thought? Language & Communication, 9(2–3), 99–106.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  56. Haugeland, J. (1993). Mind embodied and embedded. In Y.-H. H. Houng, J. Ho (Eds.), Mind and cognition: 1993 international symposium (pp. 233–267) Academica Sinica.Google Scholar
  57. Haugeland, J. (2000). Having thought: Essays in the metaphysics of mind (New ed.). Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  58. Hempel, C. (1966). Philosophy of natural science. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.Google Scholar
  59. Hempel, C. (1970). Aspects of scientific explanation. New York: The Free Press.Google Scholar
  60. Heylighen, F., Heath, M., & Van Overwalle, F. (2007). The emergence of distributed cognition: A conceptual framework. In Proceedings of collective intentionality IV (2004), Vol. IV. University of Siena.Google Scholar
  61. Hutchins, E. (1995). Cognition in the wild. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  62. Kaiser, D. (2005). Physics and Feynman’s diagrams. American Scientist, 93(2), 156.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  63. Kirk, R. (2011). Zombies. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.Google Scholar
  64. Klein, U. (1999). Techniques of modeling and paper-tools in classical chemistry. In M. Morgan & M. Morrison (Eds.), Models as mediators: Perspectives on the natural and social science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  65. Knorr-Cetina, K. (1999). Epistemic cultures: How the sciences make knowledge. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  66. Kuhn, T. S. (1962). The structure of scientific revolutions. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  67. Lakatos, I. (1970). Falsification and the methodology of scientific research programmes. In Imre Lakatos Alan Musgrave (Ed.), Criticism and the growth of knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  68. Latour, B., & Woolgar, S. (1986). Laboratory life: The construction of scientific facts. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  69. Latour, B. (1999). Pandora’s hope: An essay on the reality of science studies. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  70. Latour, B. (2007). Reassembling the social: An introduction to actor-network-theory (New Ed ed.). Oxford: OUP Oxford.Google Scholar
  71. Levine, J. (1983). Materialism and qualia: The explanatory gap. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 64, 354–361.Google Scholar
  72. Linell, P. (2005). The written language bias in linguistics. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  73. List, C., & Pettit, P. (2006). Group agency and supervenience. The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 44(S1), 85–105. doi: 10.1111/j.2041-6962.2006.tb00032.x.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  74. List, C. (2011). Group agency: The possibility, design, and status of corporate agents. Oxford: OUP Oxford.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  75. Logan, K.R. (2003). The extended mind: Understanding language and thought in terms of complexity and Chaos Theory. In D. McArthur & C. Mulvihil (Eds.) Humanity and the Cosmos. Retrieved http://www.upscale.utoronto.ca/PVB/Logan/Extended/Extended.html.
  76. Logan, K. R. (2006). The extended mind model of the origin of language and culture. In N. Gontier, et al. (Eds.), Evolutionary epistemology and culture (pp. 149–167). New York: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  77. Logan, K. R. (2008). The extended mind: The emergence of language, the human mind and culture. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.Google Scholar
  78. Markie, P. (2013). Rationalism vs. empiricism. In: E.N. Zalta (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Summer 2013.) Retrieved http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2013/entries/rationalism-empiricism/.
  79. McClelland et al. (1986). In J.L. McClelland, D.E. Rumelhart & the PDP Research Group (Eds.), Parallel distributed processing : Explorations in the microstructure of cognition, vol. 2. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  80. McGinn, C. (1989). Can we solve the mind-body problem? Mind, 98, 349–66.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  81. McGinn, C. (1991). The problem of consciousness. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  82. Menary, R. (2006). Attacking the bounds of cognition. Philosophical Psychology, 19(3), 329–344.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  83. Menary, R. (2007). Cognitive integration: Mind and cognition unbound. Basingstoke: Palgrave McMillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  84. Menary, R. (2013). Cognitive integration, enculturated cognition and the socially extended mind. Cognitive Systems Research, 25–26, 26–34. doi: 10.1016/j.cogsys.2013.05.002.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  85. Morgan, M., & Morrison, M. (1999). Models as mediators: Perspectives on the natural and social science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  86. Olson, D. R. (1996a). Language and literacy: What writing does to language and mind. Annual Review of Applied Linguistics, 16, 3–13.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  87. Olson, D. R. (1996b). The world on paper: The conceptual and cognitive implications of writing and reading. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  88. Olson, D. R. (2002). What writing does to the mind. In E. Amsel & J. P. Byrnes (Eds.), Language, literacy, and cognitive development: The development and consequences of symbolic communication. New York: Psychology Press.Google Scholar
  89. Palermos, S. O. (2011). Belief-forming processes, extended. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 2, 741–765.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  90. Palermos, S.O. (2013). Could reliability naturally imply safety?. European Journal of Philosophy. doi: 10.1111/ejop.12046.
  91. Palermos, S. O., & Pritchard, D. (2013). Extended knowledge and social epistemology. Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective, 2(8), 105–120.Google Scholar
  92. Palermos, S. O. (2014a). Loops, constitution, and cognitive extension. Cognitive Systems Research, 27, 25–41.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  93. Palermos, S. O. (2014). Knowledge and cognitive integration. Synthese, 191(8), 1931–1951.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  94. Pettit, P. (2002). Collective reasons and powers. Legal Theory, 8(04), 443–470.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  95. Popper, K. R. (1968). Epistemology without a knowing subject. In B. van Rootselaar & J. F. Staal (Eds.), Proceedings of the third international congress for logic, methodology and philosophy of science. Amsterdam. (Reprinted in K. R. Popper. (1972). Objective knowledge: An evolutionary approach. Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
  96. Pritchard, D. (2010b). Cognitive ability and the extended cognition thesis. Synthese, 175, 133–151.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  97. Pritchard, D. (2010a). Knowledge and understanding. In A. Haddock, A. Millar, & D. H. Pritchard (Eds.), The nature and value of knowledge. Three Investigations, Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  98. Putnam, H. (1975). The meaning of “Meaning”. In K. Gunderson (Ed.), Language, mind and knowledge. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
  99. Rolin, K. (2008). Science as collective knowledge. Cognitive Systems Research, 9(1–2), 115–124. doi: 10.1016/j.cogsys.2007.07.007.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  100. Rowlands, M. (1999). The body in mind: Understanding cognitive processes. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  101. Rupert, R. D. (2004). Challenges to the hypothesis of extended cognition. Journal of Philosophy, 101(8), 389–428.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  102. Rupert, R. D. (2009). Cognitive systems and the extended mind (1st ed.). Oxford: OUP USA.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  103. Saussure, F. (1916/1983). Course in general Linguistics. Duckworth. (Roy Harris, Trans.).Google Scholar
  104. Seibt, J. (2012). Process Philosophy. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Fall 2013 Edition). Retrieved http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2013/entries/process-philosophy/.
  105. Shani, I. (2013). Making it mental: In search for the golden mean of the extended cognition controversy. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 12(1), 1–26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  106. Shankweiler, D., & Liberman, I. (1972). Misreading: A search for causes. In J. Kavanagh & I. Mattingly (Eds.), Language by ear and by eye; the relationships between speech and reading (pp. 293–317). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  107. Sosa, E. (1988). Beyond skepticism, to the best of our knowledge. Mind, New Series, 97(386), 153–188.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  108. Sosa, E. (1993). Proper functionalism and virtue epistemology. Nous, 27(1), 51–65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  109. Sosa, E. (2007). A virtue epistemology: Apt belief and reflective knowledge. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  110. Suppe, F. (1977). The structure of scientific theories. Chicago: University of Illinois Press.Google Scholar
  111. Suppes, O. (1961). A comparison of the meaning and use of models in the mathematical and empirical sciences. In H. Freudenthal (Ed.), The concept and role of the model in mathematics and natural and social sciences (pp. 163–177). Dordrecht: Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  112. Suppes, O. (1967). What is a scientific theory? In S. Morgenbesser (Ed.), Philosophy of science today (pp. 55–67). New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
  113. Sutton, J., Barnier, A., Harris, C., & Wilson, R. (2008). A conceptual and empirical framework for the social distribution of cognition: The case of memory. Cognitive Systems Research, 9(1—-2), 35–51.Google Scholar
  114. Sutton, J. (2008). Between individual and collective memory: Coordination, interaction, distribution. Social Research, 75(1), 23–48.Google Scholar
  115. Theiner, G. (2013). Language, literacy, and media theory: Exploring the cultural history of the extended mind. AVANT. Journal of the Philosophical-Interdisciplinary Vanguard, 4(2).Google Scholar
  116. Theiner, G., & Wilson, R. (2013). Group mind. Encyclopedia of Philosophy and the Social Sciences.Google Scholar
  117. Theiner, G., Allen, C., & Goldstone, R. (2010). Recognizing group cognition. Cognitive Systems Research, 11(4), 378–395.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  118. Theiner, G., & O’Connor, T. (2010). The emergence of group cognition. In A. Corradini & T. O’Connor (Eds.), Emergence in science and philosophy (pp. 6–78). London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  119. Theiner, G. (2011). Res cogitans extensa: A philosophical defense of the extended mind thesis. Bern: Peter Lang GmbH, Europaischer Verlag der Wissenschaften.Google Scholar
  120. Tollefsen, D. (2004). Collective intentionality. Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.Google Scholar
  121. Tollefsen, D. (2002a). Organizations as true believers. Journal of Social Philosophy, 33(3), 395–410.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  122. Tollefsen, D. (2002b). Collective intentionality and the social sciences. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 32(1), 25–50. doi: 10.1177/004839310203200102.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  123. Tollefsen, D. (2006). From extended mind to collective mind. Cognitive Systems Research, 7(2–3), 140–150.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  124. Tollefsen, D., & Dale, R. (2011). Naturalizing joint action: A process-based approach. Philosophical Psychology, 25, 385–407.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  125. Tomasello, M. (2009). The cultural origins of human cognition. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  126. Tufte, E. R. (2001). The visual display of quantitative information (2nd ed.). Cheshire, Conn: Graphics Press USA.Google Scholar
  127. Tuomela, R., & Miller, K. (1988). We-intentions. Philosophical Studies, 53(3), 367–389. doi: 10.1007/BF00353512.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  128. Tuomela, R. (2004). Group knowledge analyzed. Episteme, 1(2), 109–127.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  129. van Fraassen, B. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  130. van Gelder, T. (1995). What might cognition be if not computation? Journal of Philosophy, 92(7), 81–345.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  131. Van Gulick, R. (2004). Consciousness. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.Google Scholar
  132. Vygotsky, L. (1978). Mind in society: Development of higher psychological processes (New ed.). Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  133. Vygotsky, L. (1986). Thought and language (2 Revised ed.). Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  134. Wegner, D., Giuliano, T., & Hertel, P. (1985). Cognitive interdependence in close relationships. In W. J. Ickes (Ed.), Compatible and incompatible relationships (pp. 253–276). New York: Springer-Verlag.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  135. Wegner, D. (1986). Transactive memory: A contemporary analysis of the group mind. In B. Mullen & G. R. Goethals (Eds.), Theories of group behavior. New York: Springer-Verlag.Google Scholar
  136. Weiskopf, D. A. (2007). Concept empiricism and the vehicles of thought. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 14(s 9–10), 156–183.Google Scholar
  137. Wertsch, J. V. (1988). Vygotsky and the social formation of mind (Reprint ed.). Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  138. Wheeler, M. (2005). Reconstructing the cognitive world. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  139. Wilson, R. A. (2000). The mind beyond itself. In D. Sperber (Ed.), Metarepresentations: A multidisciplinary perspective (pp. 31–52). New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  140. Wilson, R. (2001a). Two views of realization. Philosophical Studies, 104, 1–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  141. Wilson, R. (2001b). Group-level cognition. Philosophy of Science, 68(3), 262–273.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  142. Wilson, R. (2004). Boundaries of the mind: The individual in the fragile sciences: Cognition. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  143. Wilson, R. (2005). Collective memory, group minds, and the extended mind thesis. Cognitive Processing, 6(4), 227–236.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  144. Wray, K. B. (2007). Who has scientific knowledge? Social Epistemology, 21(3), 337–347. doi: 10.1080/02691720701674288.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  145. Zagzebski, L. T. (1996). Virtues of the mind: An inquiry into the nature of virtue and the ethical foundations of knowledge. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2015

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Extended Knowledge Project, Department of Philosophy, School of Philosophy, Psychology and the Language Sciences, Eidyn CentreUniversity of EdinburghEdinburghScotland, UK

Personalised recommendations