Springer Nature is making SARS-CoV-2 and COVID-19 research free. View research | View latest news | Sign up for updates

Carnap on empirical significance

  • 579 Accesses

  • 3 Citations

Abstract

Carnap’s search for a criterion of empirical significance is usually considered a failure. I argue that the results from two out of his three different approaches are at the very least problematic, but that one approach led to success. Carnap’s criterion of translatability into logical syntax is too vague to allow for definite results. His criteria for terms—introducibility by chains of reduction sentences and his criterion from “The Methodological Character of Theoretical Concepts”—are almost trivial and have no clear relation to the empirical significance of sentences. However, his criteria for sentences—translatability, verifiability, falsifiability, confirmability—are usable, and under the assumptions needed for the Carnap sentence approach, verifiability, falsifiability, and translatability become equivalent. As a result of the Carnap sentence approach, metaphysics is rendered analytic.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in to check access.

Fig. 1

Notes

  1. 1.

    More or less in keeping with Carnap’s and common terminology, I will use ‘term’ synonymously with ‘non-logical symbol’.

  2. 2.

    Arthur Pap translates the title more loosely as “The Elimination of Metaphysics Through Logical Analysis of Language” (Carnap 1959b).

  3. 3.

    Rolf A. George’s translation of the Aufbau (Carnap 1928a) uses the more literal translations ‘object sphere’ for ‘type’ (Carnap 1967a, §29), and ‘confusion of spheres’ for ‘type confusion’ (§30).

  4. 4.

    Note that the translation into logical syntax is different from the translation into the formal mode of speech (Carnap 1934, §74): Logical syntax is used to phrase object-sentences, which express claims of the empirical sciences, while the formal mode of speech is used to phrase syntactical sentences, which express philosophical claims.

  5. 5.

    “What is to be investigated is being only and—nothing else; being alone and further—nothing; solely being, and beyond being—nothing. What about this Nothing?” (Carnap 1931b, p. 69; cf. Heidegger 1931, pp. 9–10).

  6. 6.

    Marhenke (1949/1950) comes to the opposite conclusion because he ignores the problems with the informal translatability condition and, contrary to Carnap, assumes that inference rules are only applicable to significant sentences.

  7. 7.

    Even in Carnap’s early works, however, his later position occurs as an undercurrent (Lutz 2012, §3.6.1).

  8. 8.

    He also claims that it is in general possible to translate all scientific sentences into a variety of different basic languages, for example the physical language (Carnap 1928a, §§54–60).

  9. 9.

    Carnap (1928a, §179) of course does not think that metaphysics in the sense of “basic knowledge”, i. e., “logical, experiential, constructional order” is non-significant. In this case, however, he suggests using the terms ‘basic science’ or ‘cosmology’.

  10. 10.

    “Aber die logische Analyse kommt zu dem Ergebnis [ ...], daß die sog. metaphysischen Sätze Scheinsätze sind, da sie in keinem Ableitungsverhältnis (weder einem positiven noch einem negativen) zu den Sätzen der Protokollsprache stehen.”

  11. 11.

    “Erlebnisse, Wahrnehmungen, aber auch Gefühle, Gedanken usw.”

  12. 12.

    This terminology follows that of Hempel (1950, pp. 45–48).

  13. 13.

    As Justus’s criticism (2011, pp. 429–430) of a criterion by Sober (2008, §2.14) shows, this dilemma is still under discussion.

  14. 14.

    Note that this puts additional restrictions on protocols.

  15. 15.

    For the ground of \(S\), the equivalence can be expressed only in languages that allow disjunctions with infinitely many disjuncts.

  16. 16.

    There is an additional wrinkle whose implications I will not discuss in the following: According to Carnap (1932), it was Neurath (1932) who first suggested treating protocol sentences and system-sentences as from the same language, which suggests that Carnap assumed in earlier discussions that the protocol sentences are in one language, the remaining (“system-”)sentences in another. But Carnap already assumed in the Aufbau that all scientific terms are definable in basic terms, and thus the basic sentences are a subset of the scientific language. Thus it is not clear in what way Neurath’s suggestion was novel.

  17. 17.

    He adds: “If by verification is meant a definitive and final establishment of truth, then no (synthetic) sentence is ever verifiable, as we shall see. We can only confirm a sentence more and more.” As far as the deducibility from \(\fancyscript{B}\)-sentences is concerned, Carnap’s argument for his claim is essentially that universally quantified sentences cannot be verified. Carnap’s more general point is that \(\fancyscript{B}\)-sentences themselves are never absolutely secure and thus also holds for falsifiability (Carnap 1936, §6).

  18. 18.

    This is what Carnap (1936, pp. 433–434) seems to assume.

  19. 19.

    I thank Pierre Wagner for very helpful discussions of this publication of Carnap’s.

  20. 20.

    Carnap (1950a, §87) discusses the conditions at length.

  21. 21.

    Note the difference to Carnap’s recursive condition in “Testability and Meaning”, where the background assumptions are fixed, but (essentially) the set \(\fancyscript{B}\) changes in each recursive step.

  22. 22.

    This is not true for the strongest criterion, translatability: Assume \(\sigma \) can be translated into \(\fancyscript{B}\)-sentence \(\beta \) by \(\vartheta \) and \(\vartheta \) can be translated into \(\fancyscript{B}\)-sentence \(\beta '\) without background assumptions. If \(\fancyscript{B}\) is only restricted by the terms it contains, \(\vartheta \) is then a \(\fancyscript{B}\)-sentence and therefore \(\sigma \) itself is a \(\fancyscript{B}\)-sentence. In this case, a definition of empirical significance as recursive translatability is safe, but also pointless.

  23. 23.

    Carnap (1928a, §38) also discusses the need for “definitions in use”. As far as terms (i. e., non-logical symbols) are concerned, these are equivalent to explicit definitions because of the eliminability theorems (cf. Gupta 2009, §2.3).

  24. 24.

    The definitions of the definability of constant or function symbols additionally contain uniqueness conditions for the constants and function values, respectively. The conditions are philosophically interesting because they introduce restrictions on the sets of sentences in which constant and function symbols can be defined (Essler 1982, §14, §15; Hodges 1993, p. 59), but also introduce technical subtleties that would lead the current discussion too far afield.

  25. 25.

    Carnap also defines single reduction sentences, but these will not be relevant in the following. As in the Aufbau, Carnap (1936, §16) assumes that there are different “sufficient bases” for the reduction of scientific terms.

  26. 26.

    Carnap uses ‘reducible’ for another property of predicates. See the end of this section.

  27. 27.

    In short, ‘being empirical significant’ is a categorical predicate, while ‘the meaning of’ is a function.

  28. 28.

    Incidentally, Claim 12 can be cheaply proved by choosing \(\vartheta =\{\beta \leftrightarrow \sigma \}\) for any \(\fancyscript{B}\)-sentence \(\beta \) and any contingent sentence \(\sigma \) containing only \(\fancyscript{A}\)-terms. However, since \(\vartheta \) is a claim of purely propositional logic, this may go against the spirit of Carnap’s suggestion.

  29. 29.

    Besides explicit definitions and reduction pairs, Przełęcki (1969, Chaps. 7–8) also discusses systematic weakenings of reduction pairs.

  30. 30.

    This is just a shorthand: \(C\) stays the same, but for the recursive step, it does not matter whether a term is in \(C\) or introducible through a chain of reduction pairs on the basis of \(C\).

  31. 31.

    There could, of course, again be modifications of Carnap’s recursive step that do not trivialize his criterion, but since even the recursion base is problematic, the search may not be worth the effort.

  32. 32.

    Presumably because according to Carnap (1936, p. 447, thm. 7), it ensures that the abstract terms are reducible to elementary terms.

  33. 33.

    Each abstract term is an inus condition for \(B\) (Mackie 1980, p. 62).

  34. 34.

    The assumption that \(\vartheta \) is a conjunction is not essential.

  35. 35.

    Since Carnap (1956, pp. 51, 62) assumes that logical implication is given by semantic entailment, I use ‘\(\vDash \)’ rather than ‘\(\vdash \)’.

  36. 36.

    Note that here, too, it is the set \(K\) of terms that is recursively defined, not \(\vartheta \) (here: \(T.C\)).

  37. 37.

    Formula (3) is closely related to the method of “de-Occamization” suggested by Van Cleve (reported by Creath 1976, 397). Using Claim 14, it is easy to see that in formula (3), none of the \(\fancyscript{A}\)-terms is Carnap-significant relative to \(\varnothing \).

  38. 38.

    However, the recursion base of Creath’s criterion seems to me more promising than the full definition, because it already allows for determining whether a whole set of terms is significant. It thus could arguably be a non-trivial substitute for Carnap’s recursive definition.

  39. 39.

    In Tarski’s fortunate case, the necessary condition is so strong that it provides a sufficient condition as well.

  40. 40.

    In “Testability and Meaning”, Carnap (1937, p. 34) states that in confirmable sentences (which are used to define the principle of empiricism), “[p]redicates which are confirmable [ ...] are admitted”, but this does not mean that only confirmable predicates are admitted. As far as I can tell, Carnap (1936, p. 457, thm. 10) also proves only that a sentence containing exclusively confirmable predicates is itself confirmable. Hempel (1950, p. 51) may have intended his claim that the approach defining significant sentences via significant terms “has its origin in Carnap’s essay, Testability and Meaning” as a historical rather than logical remark. The criterion he discusses (definition 3.2), which demands that a significant sentence must contain only observable terms or those definable in observable terms, is his own. It did not originate with “Testability and Meaning”, as Soames (2003, p. 292) claims.

  41. 41.

    Accordingly, I do not agree with the optimistic evaluation of Carnap’s criterion by Justus (forthcoming), although I am optimistic about some of Carnap’s other criteria.

  42. 42.

    I thank Richard Creath for this point.

  43. 43.

    Besides this tension, the passage quoted above is connected to another lacuna. Carnap follows it up by in effect spelling out the different conditions of his criterion, and concludes with: “On the basis of the preceding considerations, I shall now give definitions for the concept of significance[.]” (Carnap 1956, p. 51). But as a first step of an explication, the determination of the explicandum, it is remarkably poor. There is no investigation of actual usage or practically clear cases as Carnap (1950a, p. 4) in his elucidation of explication demands, but rather the use of pure intuition on comparably technical matters of deductive inferences, which one may share or not. Furthermore, Carnap also does not show the criterion’s fruitfulness for the formulation of many universal statements, which is arguably the central requirement of a good explication (p. 7). Finally, Carnap provides a justification for his criterion for terms, but gives no justification at all for his criterion for sentences. (I thank Christopher French for discussions and his spirited defense of Carnap in this matter).

  44. 44.

    Psillos (2000a, §4) argues that Carnap rediscovered the Ramsey sentence while trying to generalize Craig’s theorem to type theory.

  45. 45.

    For the conjunction of two reduction pairs, Carnap (1936, §10) already describes an equivalent method in “Testability and Meaning” (cf. Carnap 1963b, pp. 964–965).

  46. 46.

    That this does not render claims of empirical significance preliminary or knowledge dependent is shown in Sect. 6.1.

  47. 47.

    The criticism by Demopoulos (2007, vii) that, essentially, the Carnap sentence renders a theory analytically equivalent to its content in \(\fancyscript{B}\) is therefore but an expression of Carnap’s conception of empiricism.

  48. 48.

    Whether his interpretation of Thomas Aquinas is correct is irrelevant for my discussion.

  49. 49.

    The term ‘God’ thus must be defined as entailing a first cause.

  50. 50.

    The discussion here and in the following ignores problems stemming from the incompleteness of deduction in higher order logic for Tarski semantics. One could avoid any such problems by switching either to semantic entailment or to Henkin semantics.

  51. 51.

    This strategy is not that uncommon, for example when \(\ulcorner x\ne y\urcorner \) is defined in the metalanguage of a logic as an abbreviation for \(\ulcorner \lnot x=y\urcorner \), without introducing a corresponding axiom into the language.

  52. 52.

    Thus it seems that “pure optatives” (proposals, requests, demands, etc. that do not assert any matters of fact) are analytic, contrary to Carnap’s claims (cf. Carnap 1963b, p. 32.b).

  53. 53.

    The recursion base of the criterion by Creath (1976) may fit the bill.

References

  1. Adams, C. (2011a). Is there a God? Archived by WebCite\(^{\textregistered }\) at http://www.webcitation.org/6PC0xRqj6, Chicago Reader, November 11. http://www.straightdope.com/columns/read/3021/is-there-a-god.

  2. Adams, C. (2011b). Is there a God (revisited)? Archived by WebCite\(^{\textregistered }\) at http://www.webcitation.org/6PC13RKoE, Chicago Reader, December 2. http://www.straightdope.com/columns/read/3025/is-there-a-god-revisited.

  3. Ayer, A. J. (1936). Language, truth and logic (1st ed.). References are to the second edition (Ayer 1946). London: Victor Gollanz.

  4. Ayer, A. J. (1946). Language, truth and logic (2nd ed.). London: Victor Gollanz.

  5. Ayer, A. J. (Ed.). (1959). Logical positivism. New York: The Free Press.

  6. Belnap, N. (1993). On rigorous definitions. Philosophical Studies, 72, 115–146.

  7. Benson, A. J. (1963). Bibliography of the writings of Rudolf Carnap. In Schilpp 1963 (pp. 1016–1070).

  8. Carnap, R. (1928a). Der logische Aufbau der Welt. References are to the translation (Carnap 1967a). Berlin-Schlachtensee: Weltkreis-Verlag.

  9. Carnap, R. (1928b). Scheinprobleme in der Philosophie: Das Fremdpsychische und der Realismusstreit. References are to the translation (Carnap 1967a). Berlin-Schlachtensee: Weltkreis-Verlag.

  10. Carnap, R. (1931a). Die physikalische Sprache als Universalsprache der Wissenschaft. Nominal publication date incorrect. Published in 1932. Erkenntnis, 2(5/6), 432–465.

  11. Carnap, R. (1931b). Überwindung der Metaphysik durch logische Analyse der Sprache. Nominal publication date incorrect. Published in 1932. References are to the translation (Carnap 1959b). Erkenntnis, 2 (4).

  12. Carnap, R. (1932). Über Protokollsätze. References are to the translation (Carnap 1987). Erkenntnis, 3(1), 215–228.

  13. Carnap, R. (1932/1933). Psychologie in physikalischer Sprache. References are to the translation (Carnap 1959a). Erkenntnis, 3(1), 107–142.

  14. Carnap, R. (1934). Logische Syntax der Sprache (Vol. 8). Schriften zur wissenschaftlichen Weltauffassung. References are to the corrected translation (Carnap 1967b). Wien: Springer-Verlag.

  15. Carnap, R. (1935). Philosophy and logical syntax. Psyche Miniatures, General Series 70. London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner & Co.

  16. Carnap, R. (1936). Testability and meaning. Philosophy of Science, 3(4), 420–468.

  17. Carnap, R. (1937). Testability and meaning—Continued. Philosophy of Science, 4(1), 2–35.

  18. Carnap, R. (1938). Empiricism and the language of science. Synthese, 3(1).

  19. Carnap, R. (1939). Foundations of logic and mathematics (Vol. I, No. 3, pp. 139–213). Foundations of the unity of science. Toward an International Encyclopedia of Unified Science. References are to the two-volume edition. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

  20. Carnap, R. (1950a). Logical foundations of probability. References are to the second edition (Carnap 1962). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

  21. Carnap, R. (1950b). Testability and meaning. New Haven, CT: Yale University.

  22. Carnap, R. (1956). The methodological character of theoretical concepts. In H. Feigl & M. Scriven (Eds.), The foundations of science and the concepts of psychology and psychoanalysis (Vol. 1, pp. 38–75). Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.

  23. Carnap, R. (1958). Beobachtungssprache und theoretische Sprache. Dialectica, 12(3–4), 236–248.

  24. Carnap, R. (1959a). Psychology in physical language.Translated by G. Schick. In A. J. Ayer (Ed.), Logical positivism (pp. 165–198). New York: Free Press.

  25. Carnap, R. (1959b). The elimination of metaphysics through logical analysis of language.Translated by A. Pap. In A. J. Ayer (Ed.), Logical positivism (pp. 60–81). New York: The Free Press.

  26. Carnap, R. (1962). Logical foundations of probability (2nd ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

  27. Carnap, R. (1963a). Intellectual autobiography. In Schilpp 1963 (pp. 1–84). La Salle, IL: The Open Court.

  28. Carnap, R. (1963b). Replies and systematic expositions. In Schilpp 1963 (pp. 859–1016). La Salle, IL: The Open Court.

  29. Carnap, R. (1967a). The logical structure of the world. Pseudoproblems of philosophy. Translated by R. A. George. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.

  30. Carnap, R. (1967b). The logical syntax of language. Translated by A. Smeaton. Reprinted with corrections. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul Ltd.

  31. Carnap, R. (1987). On protocol sentences. Translated by R. Creath & R. Nollan. \(No{\hat{u}}s, 21\)(4), 457–470.

  32. Church, A. (1949). Review: Alfred Jules Ayer, Language, truth, and logic (2nd ed.). The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 14(1), 52–53.

  33. Creath, Richard. (1976). On Kaplan on Carnap on significance. Philosophical Studies, 30, 393–400.

  34. Demopoulos, W. (2007). Carnap on the rational reconstruction of scientific theories. In M. Friedman & R. Creath (Eds.), The Cambridge compation to Carnap (pp. 248–272). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  35. Diamond, M. L. (1975). The challenge of contemporary empiricism. Diamond and Litzenburg, 1975, 3–62.

  36. Diamond, M. L., & Litzenburg, T. V. (Eds.). (1975). The logic of God: Theology and verification. Indianapolis, IN: Bobbs-Merill.

  37. Essler, W. K. (1982). Wissenschaftstheorie I. Definition und Reduktion. In Kolleg Philosophie (2nd ed.). München: Verlag Karl Alber.

  38. Flew, A. (1950). Theology and falsification. References are to the reprint (Diamond and Litzenburg, 1975, 257–259). University, 1, 1–8.

  39. Friedl, J., & Rutte, H. (2008). Meaning and verification—Editorischer Bericht. In: Die Wiener Zeit. Aufsätze, Beiträge, Rezensionen 1926–1936, I.6:703–708. Moritz Schlick. Gesamtausgabe. Edited and with introductions by Johannes Friedl and Heiner Rutte. Wien: Springer-Verlag.

  40. Goodman, N. (1965). Fact, fiction, and forecast (2nd ed.). Indianapolis, IN: Bobbs- Merrill.

  41. Gupta, A. (2009). Definitions. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, Spring 2009. Stanford, CA: The Metaphysics Research Lab, Center for the Study of Language and Information, Stanford University.

  42. Heidegger, M. (1931). Was ist Metaphysik?. Bonn: Verlag von Friedrich Cohen.

  43. Hempel, C. G. (1945). Studies in the logic of confirmation (II.). Mind, 54(214), 97–121.

  44. Hempel, C. G. (1950). Problems and changes in the empiricist criterion of meaning. Revue Internationale de Philosophie, 11, 41–63.

  45. Hempel, Carl G. (1951). The concept of cognitive significance: A reconsideration. Proceedings of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences, 80(1), 61–77.

  46. Hempel, C. G. (1958). The theoretician’s dilemma. In: H. Feigl, M. Scriven, & G. Maxwell (Eds.), Concepts, theories, and the mind-body problem (Vol. 2, pp. 173–226). Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.

  47. Hodges, W. (1993). Model theory. In Encyclopedia of mathematics and its applications (Vol. 42). Digitally printed in 2008. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  48. Howson, C., & Urbach, P. (1993). Scientific reasoning: The Bayesian approach (2nd ed.). Second printing 1996. Chicago: Open Court.

  49. Justus, J. (forthcoming). Carnap’s forgotten criterion of empirical significance. Mind. doi:10.1093/mind/fzu042.

  50. Justus, J. (2011). Evidentiary inference in evolutionary biology. Review of (Sober 2008). Biology and Philosophy, 26, 419–437. doi:10.1007/s10539-010-9205-7.

  51. Kaplan, D. (1975). Significance and analyticity: A comment on some recent proposals of Carnap. In J. Hintikka (Ed.), Rudolph Carnap, logical empiricist: Materials and perspectives. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

  52. Lewis, D. (1988a). Ayer’s first empiricist criterion of meaning: Why does it fail? Analysis, 48(1), 1–3.

  53. Lewis, D. (1988b). Statements partly about observation. References are to the reprint (Lewis 1998, 125–155). Philosophical Papers, 17, 1–31.

  54. Lewis, D. (1998). Papers in philosophical logic. Cambridge Studies in Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  55. Lutz, S. (2012). Criteria of empirical significance: foundations, relations, applications. PhD dissertation, Utrecht University. http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/id/eprint/9117.

  56. Mackie, J. L. (1980). The cement of the universe. A study of causation (2nd ed.). Reprinted 2002. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

  57. Malzkorn, W. (2001). Defining disposition concepts: A brief history of the problem. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 32(2), 335–353.

  58. Marhenke, P. (1949/1950). The criterion of significance. Proceedings and addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 23, 1–21.

  59. Mormann, T. (2007). Carnap’s logical empiricism, values, and American pragmatism. Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 38, 127–146. doi:10.1007/s10838-007-9033-x.

  60. Neurath, O. (1932). Protokollsätze. Erkenntnis, 3(1), 204–214.

  61. Pokriefka, M. L. (1983). Ayer’s definition of empirical significance revisited. Analysis, 43(4), 166–170.

  62. Pokriefka, M. L. (1984). More on empirical significance. Analysis, 44(2), 92–93.

  63. Przełęcki, M. (1969). The logic of empirical theories. Monographs in Modern Logic Series. London/New York: Routledge & Kegan Paul/Humanities Press.

  64. Psillos, S. (2000a). Carnap, the Ramsey-sentence and realistic empiricism. Erkenntnis, 52, 253–279. doi:10.1023/a:1005589117656.

  65. Psillos, S. (2000b). Rudolf Carnap’s theoretical concepts in science. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 31(1), 151–172. doi:10.1016/s0039-3681(99)00031-x.

  66. Reichenbach, H. (1951). The verifiability theory of meaning. Proceedings of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences, 80(1), 46–60.

  67. Rozeboom, W. W. (1962). The factual content of theoretical concepts. In H. Feigl, M. Scriven, & G. Maxwell (Eds.), Scientific explanation, space, and time (Vol. 3, pp. 273–357). Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.

  68. Ruja, H. (1961). The present status of the verifiability criterion. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 22(2), 216–222.

  69. Schilpp, P. A. (Ed.). (1963). The philosophy of Rudolf Carnap. In The library of living philosophers (Vol. 11). Chicago: Open Court Publishing Company.

  70. Schurz, G. (2014). Philosophy of science. A unified approach. New York: Routledge.

  71. Skyrms, B. (1984). Prediction and experience. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

  72. Soames, S. (2003). The dawn of analysis. In Philosophical analysis in the twentieth century (Vol. 1). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

  73. Sober, E. (2008). Evidence and evolution: The logic behind the science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  74. Van Cleve, J. (1971). Empiricist criteria of meaningfulness. Unpublished, cited by Creath (1976).

  75. Wagner, P. (2014). Quel empirisme? Le projet de Carnap dans Testabilité et signification. In: Testabilité et signification, by Rudolf Carnap, translated by Yann Benétreau-Dupin, 7–53. Translation of (Carnap 1936, 1937). Paris: Vrin.

  76. Winnie, J. A. (1970). Theoretical analyticity. In R. C. Buck & R. S. Cohen (Eds.), In Memory of Rudolf Carnap: Proceedings of the biennial meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association (Vol. VIII, pp. 289–305). Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science. Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Company.

  77. Wright, C. (1986). Scientific realism, observation and the verification principle. In G. Macdonald & C. Wright (Eds.), Fact, science and morality: Essays on A. J. Ayer’s language, truth and logic (pp. 247–274). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

  78. Wright, C. (1989). The verification principle: Another puncture–another patch. Mind, 98(392), 611–622.

  79. Yi, B.-U. (2001). Compact entailment and Wright’s verification principle. Mind, 110(437), 414–421.

Download references

Acknowledgments

A previous version was presented in 2013 at the workshop Carnap on Logic at the Ludwig-Maximilians-Universität München, some aspects were presented in 2013 at the workshop Formal Epistemology and the Legacy of Logical Empiricism at the University of Texas at Austin and in 2012 at the Groningen/Munich Summer School Formal Methods in Philosophy under the title “The Criteria for the Empirical Significance of Terms”. I thank the audiences for helpful comments and discussions, and I especially thank two anonymous reviewers for a multitude of excellent comments, corrections, and suggestions. Research for this article was supported by the Alexander von Humboldt Foundation.

Author information

Correspondence to Sebastian Lutz.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and Permissions

About this article

Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Lutz, S. Carnap on empirical significance. Synthese 194, 217–252 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-014-0561-8

Download citation

Keywords

  • Empirical significance
  • Carnap
  • Logical empiricism
  • Carnap sentence
  • Verifiability
  • Falsifiability