Advertisement

Synthese

, Volume 191, Issue 17, pp 4201–4229 | Cite as

An empirically feasible approach to the epistemology of arithmetic

  • Markus PantsarEmail author
Article

Abstract

Recent years have seen an explosion of empirical data concerning arithmetical cognition. In this paper that data is taken to be philosophically important and an outline for an empirically feasible epistemological theory of arithmetic is presented. The epistemological theory is based on the empirically well-supported hypothesis that our arithmetical ability is built on a protoarithmetical ability to categorize observations in terms of quantities that we have already as infants and share with many nonhuman animals. It is argued here that arithmetical knowledge developed in such a way cannot be totally conceptual in the sense relevant to the philosophy of arithmetic, but neither can arithmetic understood to be empirical. Rather, we need to develop a contextual a priori notion of arithmetical knowledge that preserves the special mathematical characteristics without ignoring the roots of arithmetical cognition. Such a contextual a priori theory is shown not to require any ontologically problematic assumptions, in addition to fitting well within a standard framework of general epistemology.

Keywords

Arithmetical cognition Philosophy of mathematics Epistemology Empirical study Contextual a priori 1 

Notes

Acknowledgments

This work has been made possible by the generous support of the Academy of Finland and the University of Bucharest. I am in great gratitude to the many colleagues who have provided valuable comments on the manuscript at some point, especially Daniel Cohnitz and Dirk Schlimm.

References

  1. Agrillo, C., Dadda, M., Serena, G., & Bisazza, A. (2009). Use of number by fish. PLoS One, 4(3), e4786.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Azzouni, J. (2010). Talking about nothing—Numbers, hallucinations and fiction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Boghossian, P., & Peacocke, C. (2000). New essays on the a priori. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Brannon, E., & Merritt, D. (2011). Evolutionary foundations of the approximate number system. In Dehaene (Ed.), Space, time and number in the brain (pp. 107–122). London: Academic Press.Google Scholar
  5. Burge, T. (2007). Postscript to “Belief de re” in foundations of mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  6. Burge, T. (2010). Origins of objectivity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Butterworth, B. (2010). Foundational numerical capacities and the origins of dyscalculia. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 14, 534–541.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Cantlon, J. F., & Brannon, E. M. (2006). Shared system for ordering small and large numbers in monkeys and humans. Psychological Science, 17(5), 402–407.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Carey, S. (2009a). Where our number concepts come from. The Journal of Philosophy, 106(4), 220–254.Google Scholar
  10. Carey, S. (2009b). The origin of concepts. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Church, R., & Meck, W. (1984). The numerical attribute of stimuli. In H. L. Roitblat, T. G. Bever, & H. S. Terrace (Eds.), Animal cognition (pp. 445–464). Hillsdale: Erlbaum.Google Scholar
  12. Clarke-Doane, J. (2012). Morality and mathematics: The evolutionary challenge. Ethics, 122(2), 313–340.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Dehaene, S. (2011). Number sense (2nd ed.). New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  14. Dehaene, S., & Brannon, E. (Eds.). (2011). Space, time and number in the brain. London: Academic Press.Google Scholar
  15. Diester, I., & Nieder, A. (2007). Semantic associations between signs and numerical categories in the prefrontal cortex. PLoS Biology, 5, e294.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Dummett, M. (1973). Frege: Philosophy of language. London: Duckworth.Google Scholar
  17. Essenin-Volpin, A. (1961). Le Programme Ultra-intuitionniste des fondements des mathématiques. Infinistic methods (pp. 201–223). New York: Pergamon Press.Google Scholar
  18. Feigenson, L. (2011). Objects, sets, and ensembles. In Dehaene & Brennan (Eds.), Space, time and number in the brain (pp. 13–22). London: Academic Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Field, H. (1980). Science without numbers: A defense of nominalism. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  20. Field, H. (1998). Mathematical objectivity and mathematical objects. In S. Laurence & C. Macdonald (Eds.), Contemporary readings in the foundations of metaphysics (pp. 387–403). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
  21. Gödel, K. (1947). What is Cantor’s continuum problem? The American Mathematical Monthly, 54, 515–25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Gordon, P. (2004). Numerical cognition without words: Evidence from Amazonia. Science, 306, 496–499.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Hellman, G. (1989). Mathematics without numbers. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  24. Ifrah, G. (1998). The universal history of numbers: From prehistory to the invention of the computer. Great Britain: The Harvill Press.Google Scholar
  25. Kitcher, P. (1983). The nature of mathematical knowledge. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  26. Kuhn, T. (1993). Afterwords. In Paul Horwich (Ed.), World changes (pp. 331–332). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  27. Lakoff, G., & Núñez, R. (2000). Where mathematics comes from. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
  28. Lavine, S. (1994). Understanding the infinite. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  29. Leslie, A. M., et al. (2008). The generative basis of natural number concepts. Trends in Cognitive Science, 12, 213–218.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Lourenco, S., & Longo, M. (2011). Origins and development of generalized magnitude representation. In Dehaene & Brennan (Eds.), Space, time and number in the brain (pp. 225–241). London: Academic Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Mechner, F. (1958). Probability relations within response sequences under ratio reinforcement. Journal of Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 1, 109–21.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Mechner, F., & Guevrekian, L. (1962). Effects of deprivation upon counting and timing in rats. Journal of Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 5, 463–66.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Mix, K. (2002). Trying to build on shifting sand: Commentary on Cohen and Marks. Developmental Science, 5, 205–206.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Mix, K., et al. (2002). Multiple cues for quantification in infancy: Is number one of them? Psychological Bulletin, 128, 278–294.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Nieder, A. (2011). The neural code for number. In S. Dehaene & E. Brannon (Eds.), Space, time and number in the brain (pp. 107–122). London: Academic Press.Google Scholar
  36. Nieder, A. (2012). Supramodal numerosity selectivity of neurons in primate prefrontal and posterior parietal cortices. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 109, 11860–11865.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Nieder, A. (2013). Coding of abstract quantity by ’number neurons’ of the primate brain. Journal of Comparative Psychology A, 199, 1–16.Google Scholar
  38. Nieder, A., et al. (2006). Temporal and spatial enumeration processes in the primate parietal cortex. Science, 313(2006), 1431–1435.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Nieder, A., & Dehaene, S. (2009). Representation of number in the brain. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 32, 185–208.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Nieder, A., Freedman, D., & Miller, E. (2002). Representations of the quantity of visual items in the primate prefrontal cortex. Science, 297, 1708–1711.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Nieder, A., & Miller, E. (2003). Coding of cognitive magnitude. Compressed scaling of numerical information in the primate prefrontal cortex. Neuron, 37, 149–157.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Piazza, M. (2010). Neurocognitive start-up tools for symbolic number representations. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 14, 542–551.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Piazza, M., et al. (2007). A magnitude code common to numerosities and number symbols in human intraparietal cortex. Neuron, 53, 293–305.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. Piazza, M., et al. (2013). Education enhances the acuity of nonverbal approximate number system. Psychological Science, 24, 1037–1043.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. Putnam, H. (1968). Is logic empirical? In Boston studies in the philosophy of science, vol. 5, D (pp. 216–241). Dordrecht: Reidel. Google Scholar
  46. Putnam, H. (1980). Models and reality. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 45, 464–482.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. Putnam, H. (1983). ‘Two dogmas’ revisited. In Realism and reason: Philosophical papers (Vol. 3, pp. 87–97). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  48. Putnam, H. (2004). Ethics without ontology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  49. Quine, W. V. O. (1951). Two dogmas of empiricism. In From a logical point of view. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  50. Resnik, M. (1981). Mathematics as a science of patterns: Ontology and reference. Nous, 15, 529–550.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  51. Rumbaugh, D., Savage-Rumbaugh, S., & Hegel, M. (1987). Summation in the chimpanzee. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Animal Behavior Processes, 13, 107–115.Google Scholar
  52. Ruse, M. (1986). Taking Darwin seriously: A naturalistic approach to philosophy. New York: Prometheus Book.Google Scholar
  53. Shapiro, S. (1997). Philosophy of mathematics: Structure and ontology. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  54. Simon, T. J., Hespos, S. J., & Rochat, P. (1995). Do infants understand simple arithmetic? A replication of Wynn (1992). Cognitive Development, 10, 253–269.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  55. Spelke, E. (2011). Natural number and natural geometry. In S. Dehaene & E. Brannon (Eds.), Space, time and number in the brain (pp. 287–318). London: Academic Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  56. Street, S. (2006). A Darwinian dilemma for realist theories of value. Philosophical Studies, 127, 109–166.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  57. Wynn, K. (1992). Addition and subtraction by human infants. Nature, 358, 749–751.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2014

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of Philosophy, History, Culture and Art StudiesUniversity of HelsinkiHelsinkiFinland

Personalised recommendations