Synthese

, Volume 191, Issue 15, pp 3733–3758 | Cite as

A conditional logic for abduction

Article

Abstract

We propose a logic of abduction that (i) provides an appropriate formalization of the explanatory conditional, and that (ii) captures the defeasible nature of abductive inference. For (i), we argue that explanatory conditionals are non-classical, and rely on Brian Chellas’s work on conditional logics for providing an alternative formalization of the explanatory conditional. For (ii), we make use of the adaptive logics framework for modeling defeasible reasoning. We show how our proposal allows for a more natural reading of explanatory relations, and how it overcomes problems faced by other systems in the literature.

Keywords

Abduction Adaptive logics Conditional logic Non-monotonic logic 

References

  1. Aliseda, A. (2006). Abductive reasoning logical investigations into discovery and explanations. Berlin: Springer, Synthese Library.Google Scholar
  2. Aliseda, A., & Leonides, L. (2013). Hypotheses testing in adaptive logics: An application to medical diagnosis. Logic Journal of the IGPL, 21, 915–930.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Batens, D. (2000). A survey of inconsistency-adaptive logics. In D. Batens, G. Priest, & J-Pl van Bendegem (Eds.), Frontiers of paraconsistent logic (pp. 49–73). Baldock: Research Studies Press, Kings College Publication.Google Scholar
  4. Batens, D. (2007). A universal logic approach to adaptive logics. Logica Universalis, 1, 221–242.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Ben-David, S., & Ben-Eliyahu-Zohary, R. (2000). A modal logic for subjective default reasoning. Artificial Intelligence, 116, 217–236.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Boutilier, C., & Becher, V. (1995). Abduction as belief revision. Artificial Intelligence, 77(1), 43–94.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Campos, D. (2011). On the distinction between Peirce’s abduction and Lipton’s inference to the best explanation. Synthese, 180, 419–442.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Carnielli, W. (2006). Surviving abduction. Logic Journal of IGPL, 14(2), 237–256.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Chellas, B. F. (1975). Basic conditional logic. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 4, 133–153.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Ciampolini, A., & Torroni, P. (2004). Using abductive logic agents for modeling the judicial evaluation of criminal evidence. Applied Artificial Intelligence, 18(3–4), 251–275.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Console, L., & Torasso, P. (1991). On the co-operation between abductive and temporal reasoning in medical diagnosis. Artificial Intelligence in Medicine, 3(6), 291–311.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Douven, I. (2011). Abduction. In E. N. Zalta (Ed), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2011 ed.). http://plato.stanford.edu/cgi-bin/encyclopedia/archinfo.cgi?entry=abduction.
  13. Fann, K. T. (1970). Peirce’s theory of abdcution. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Frankfurt, H. G. (1958). Peirce’s notion of abduction. The Journal of Philosophy, 55(14), 593–597.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Gauderis, T. (2013). Modelling abduction in science by means of a modal adaptive logic. Foundations of Science18(4), 611–624.Google Scholar
  16. Harman, G. (1965). The inference to the best explanation. Philosophical Review, 74, 88–95.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Hintikka, J. (1998). What is abduction? the fundamental problem of contemporary epistemology. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society, 34, 503–533.Google Scholar
  18. Hobbs, Jerry R. (2008). Abduction in natural language understanding. In L. Horn & G. Ward (Eds.), The handbook of pragmatics (pp. 724–741). Oxford: Blackwell Publishing Ltd.Google Scholar
  19. Hoffmann, M. H. G. (2011). ‘Theoric transformations’ and a new classification of abductive inferences. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society, 46, 570–590.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Horty, J. F. (2002). Skepticism and floating conclusions. Artificial Intelligence, 135, 55–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Horty, J. (2012). Reasons as defaults. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Kakas, A. C., Kowalski, R. A., & Toni, F. (1995). Abductive logic programming. Journal of Logic and Computation, 2(6), 719–770.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Lycke, H. (2012). A formal explication of the search for explanations: the adaptive logics approach to abductive reasoning. Logic Journal of IGPL, 20(2), 497–516.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Mackonis, A. (2013). Inference to the best explanation, coherence and other explanatory virtues. Synthese, 190, 975–995.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Magnani, L. (Ed.) (2013). Special issue on formal representations in model-based reasoning and abduction. Logic Journal of the IGPL, 21(6), 931–942Google Scholar
  26. Magnani, L. (2001). Abduction, reason, and science: Processes of discovery and explanation. New York: Kluwer-Plenum.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Makinson, D., & Schlechta, K. (1991). Floating conclusions and zombie paths: two deep difficulties in the “directly skeptical” approach to defeasible inheritance nets. Artificial Intelligence, 48, 199–209.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Marquis, P. (1991). Extending abduction from propositional to first-order logic. In Fundamentals of Artificial Intelligence Research (Lecture Notes in Computer Science, Vol. 535), (pp. 141–155). Berlin: Springer-Verlag.Google Scholar
  29. Mayer, M. C., & Pirri, F. (1993). First order abduction via tableau and sequent calculi. Bulletin of the IGPL, 1, 99–117.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Mayer, M. C., & Pirri, F. (1996). Abduction is not deduction-in-reverse. Logic Journal of the IGPL, 4(1), 95–108.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Meheus, J., & Batens, D. (2006). A formal logic for abductive reasoning. Logic Journal of The IGPL, 14, 221–236.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Meheus, J. (2011). A formal logic for the abduction of singular hypotheses. In D. Dieks, W. Gonzalez, S. Hartmann, T. Uebel, & M. Weber (Eds.), Explanation, prediction, and confirmation. New trends and old ones reconsidered (pp. 93–108). Berlin: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Nepomuceno-Fernández, A., Soler-Toscano, F., & Velázquez-Quesada, F. (2013). An epistemic and dynamic approach to abductive reasoning: Selecting the best explanation. Logic Journal of the IGPL, 21(6), 943–961.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Niiniluoto, I. (2000). Hempel’s theory of statistical explanation. In J. H. Fetzer (Ed.), Science, explanation, and rationality: The philosophy of Carl G. Hempel (pp. 138–163). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  35. Peirce, C. S. (1932–1958). In P. Weiss, C. Hartshorne, & A. W. Burk (Eds.). Collected papers of Charles Sanders Peirce (Vols. 1–8). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. (Abbreviated CP).Google Scholar
  36. Prendinger, H., & Ishizuka, M. (2005). A creative abduction approach to scientific and knowledge discovery. Knowledge-Based Systems, 18(7), 321–326.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Priest, G. (2008). An introduction to non-classical logic (2nd ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Psillos, S. (2002). Causation and explanation. Stocksfield: Acumen Publishing Limited.Google Scholar
  39. Psillos, S. (2002). Simply the best: a case for abduction. In A. C. Kakas & F. Sadri (Eds.), Computational logic: Logic programming and beyond (pp. 605–625). Berlin: Springer-Verlag.Google Scholar
  40. Psillos, S. (2007). Past and contemporary perspectives on explanation. In T. A. F. Kuipers (Ed.), General philosophy of science. Focal issues (pp. 97–173). Amsterdam: North-Holland Publishers.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Ruben, D.-H. (1990). Explaining explanation. London/New York: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Salmon, W. (1990). Four decades of scientific explanation. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
  43. Schurz, G. (2008). Patterns of abduction. Synthese, 164, 201–234.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. Straßer, C. (2014). Trends in Logic.Adaptive Logics for Defeasible Reasoning, Vol. 38. Berlin: Springer.Google Scholar
  45. Straßer, C. (2011). A deontic logic framework allowing for factual detachment. Journal of Applied Logic, 9(1), 61–80.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. Straßer, C. (2012). Adaptively applying modus ponens in conditional logics of normality. Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logic, 22, 125–148.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. Thagard, P. (1988). Computational Philosophy of Science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  48. Touretzky, D. S., Horty, F. J., & Thomason, R. H., (1987). A clash of intuitions: The current state of nonmonotonic multiple inheritance systems’. In Proceedings of the IJCAl-87 (pp. 476–482). Burlington, MA: Morgan Kaufmann.Google Scholar
  49. Van De Putte, F., & Straßer, C. (2013). Three formats of prioritized adaptive logics: A comparative study. Logic Journal of the IGPL, 22, 127–159.Google Scholar
  50. van Fraassen, B. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  51. Verdée, P. (2009). Adaptive logics using the minimal abnormality strategy are \(\pi ^1_1\)-complex. Synthese, 167, 93–104.Google Scholar
  52. Wilson, I. (1979). Explanatory and inferential conditionals. Philosophical Studies, 35, 269–278.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  53. Woods, J. (2012). Cognitive economics and the logic of abduction. The Review of Symbolic Logic, 5, 148–161.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2014

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Instituto de Investigaciones FilosóficasNational Autonomous University of Mexico (UNAM)Coyoacán, D.F.Mexico

Personalised recommendations