Advertisement

Synthese

, Volume 191, Issue 12, pp 2729–2750 | Cite as

They’ve lost control: reflections on skill

  • Ellen Fridland
Article

Abstract

In this paper, I submit that it is the controlled part of skilled action, that is, that part of an action that accounts for the exact, nuanced ways in which a skilled performer modifies, adjusts and guides her performance for which an adequate, philosophical theory of skill must account. I will argue that neither Jason Stanley nor Hubert Dreyfus have an adequate account of control. Further, and perhaps surprisingly, I will argue that both Stanley and Dreyfus relinquish an account of control for precisely the same reason: each reduce control to a passive, mechanistic, automatic process, which then prevents them from producing a substantive account of how controlled processes can be characterized by seemingly intelligent features and integrated with personal-level states. I will end by introducing three different kinds of control, which are constitutive of skilled action: strategic control, selective, top–down, automatic attention, and motor control. It will become clear that Dreyfus cannot account for any of these three kinds of control while Stanley has difficulty tackling the two latter kinds.

Keywords

Skill Know how Control Automaticity Intellectualism  Anti-intellectualism 

References

  1. Adams, M. (2009). Empirical evidence and the knowledge-that/knowledge-how distinction. Synthese, 170, 97–114.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Berry, D., & Broadbent, D. (1984). On the relationship between task performance and associated verbalizable knowledge. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 36(A), 209–231.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Brewer, B. (1999). Perception and reason. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  4. Brehmer, B., Hagafors, R., & Johansson, R. (1980). Cognitive skills in judgment: Subjects’ ability to use information about weights, function forms, and organizing principles. Organizational Behavior and Human Performance, 26, 373–385.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Brown, J. (2013). Knowing-how: Linguistics and cognitive science. Analysis, 73(2), 220–227.Google Scholar
  6. Chen, P. W. (1985). Restructuring versus automaticity: Alternate accounts of skill acquisition. Psychological Review, 92, 414–423.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Christensen, W., Sutton, J., & McIlwain, D. (in progress). Cognitive control in skilled action.Google Scholar
  8. Devitt, M. (2011). Methodology and the nature of knowing how. Journal of Philosophy, 108, 205–218.Google Scholar
  9. Dreyfus, H., & Dreyfus, S. (1986). Mind over machine. New York: The Free Press.Google Scholar
  10. Dreyfus, H. (2002). Intelligence without representation: Merleau Ponty’s critique of representation. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1, 367–383.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Dreyfus, H. (2007). The return of the myth of the mental. Inquiry, 50(4), 352–365.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Ericsson, K. A., & Charness, N. (1994). Expert performance: Its structure and acquisition. American Psychologist, 49, 725–774.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Frankfurt, H. (1978). The problem of action. American Philosophical Quarterly, 15(2), 157–162.Google Scholar
  14. Fridland, E. (2010). Perception and Skill: Theoretical Foundations for a Science of Perception. Dissertation, CUNY Graduate Center.Google Scholar
  15. Fridland, E. (2012). Knowing how: Problems and considerations. European Journal of Philosophy. doi: 10.1111/ejop.12000.
  16. Fridland, E. (2013a). Skill learning and conceptual thought: Making our way through the wilderness. In B. Bashour & H. Muller (Eds.), Contemporary philosophical naturalism and its implications. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  17. Fridland, E. (2013b). Problems with intellectualism. Philosophical Studies, 165(3), 879-891.Google Scholar
  18. Fodor, J. (1983). The modularity of mind. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
  19. Kirsh, D. (2013) Embodied cognition and the magical future of interaction design. ACM Transactions on Computer–Human Interaction, 20(1), article 3.Google Scholar
  20. LaBerge, D., & Samuels, S. J. (1974). Toward a theory of automatic information processing in reading. Cognitive Psychology, 6, 293–323.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Mazzoni, P., & Krakauer, J. (2006). An implicit plan overrides an explicit strategy during visuomotor adaptation. Journal of Neuroscience, 26(14), 3642–3645.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Montero, B. (2013). The myth of ‘just do it’. The stone, New York edition. New York: New York Times.Google Scholar
  23. Noë, A. (2005). Against intellectualism. Analysis, 65(4), 278–290.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Papineau, D. (2013). In the zone. In A. O’Hear (Ed.), Philosophy and sport. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  25. Pylyshyn, Z. (2003). Seeing and visualizing. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
  26. Reber, A., & Lewis, S. (1977). Implicit learning: An analysis of the form and structure of a body of tacit knowledge. Cognition, 5(1977), 333–361.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Reed, N., McLeod, P., & Dienes, Z. (2010). Implicit knowledge and motor skill: What people who know how to catch don’t know. Consciousness and Cognition, 19, 63–76.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Rey, G. (2002). Problems with Dreyfus’ dialectic. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1(4), 403–408.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Ryle, G. (1949). The concept of mind. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  30. Saling, L., & Philips, J. G. (2007). Automatic behavior: Efficient not mindless. Brain Research Bulletin, 73, 1–20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Sheets-Johnstone, M. (2003). Kinesthetic memory. Theoria et Historia Scientiarum, 7, 69–92.Google Scholar
  32. Shmuelof, L., Krakauer, J. W., & Mazzoni, P. (2012). How is a motor skill learned? Change and invariance at the levels of task success and trajectory control. Journal of Neurophysiology, 108(2), 578–594.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Stanley, J., & Williamson, T. (2001). Knowing how. Journal of Philosophy, 98(August), 411–444.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Stanley, J. (2011a). Knowing (How). Noûs, 45(2), 207–238.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Stanley, J. (2011b). Know how. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Stanley, J., & Krakauer, J. (2013). Motor skill depends on knowledge of facts. Frontiers of Human Neuroscience. doi: 10.3389/fnhum.2013.00503.
  37. Sutton, J., McIlwain, D., Christensen, W., & Geeves, A. (2011). Applying intelligence to the reflexes: Embodied skills and habits between Dreyfus and Descartes. Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology, 42(1), 78–103.Google Scholar
  38. Wallace, D. F. (2006). Federer as religious experience, Play Magazine, New York edition. New York: New York Times.Google Scholar
  39. Wallis, C. (2008). Consciousness, context and know-how. Synthese, 160, 123–153.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Williams, J. N. (2008). Propositional knowledge and know-how. Synthese, 165, 107–125.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical investigations. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  42. Wu, W. (2014). Attention. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  43. Yarbus, A. (1967). Eye movements and vision. New York: Plenum Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2014

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyKing’s College LondonLondonUK

Personalised recommendations