Synthese

, Volume 191, Issue 2, pp 213–244

Representations gone mental

Article

Abstract

Many philosophers and psychologists have attempted to elucidate the nature of mental representation by appealing to notions like isomorphism or abstract structural resemblance. The ‘structural representations’ that these theorists champion are said to count as representations by virtue of functioning as internal models of distal systems. In his 2007 book, Representation Reconsidered, William Ramsey endorses the structural conception of mental representation, but uses it to develop a novel argument against representationalism, the widespread view that cognition essentially involves the manipulation of mental representations. Ramsey argues that although theories within the ‘classical’ tradition of cognitive science once posited structural representations, these theories are being superseded by newer theories, within the tradition of connectionism and cognitive neuroscience, which rarely if ever appeal to structural representations. Instead, these theories seem to be explaining cognition by invoking so-called ‘receptor representations’, which, Ramsey claims, aren’t genuine representations at all—despite being called representations, these mechanisms function more as triggers or causal relays than as genuine stand-ins for distal systems. I argue that when the notions of structural and receptor representation are properly explicated, there turns out to be no distinction between them. There only appears to be a distinction between receptor and structural representations because the latter are tacitly conflated with the ‘mental models’ ostensibly involved in offline cognitive processes such as episodic memory and mental imagery. While structural representations might count as genuine representations, they aren’t distinctively mental representations, for they can be found in all sorts of non-intentional systems such as plants. Thus to explain the kinds of offline cognitive capacities that have motivated talk of mental models, we must develop richer conceptions of mental representation than those provided by the notions of structural and receptor representation.

Keywords

Representation Isomorphism Psychological Explanation Mental models Neural networks Feature detectors Circadian clocks Dretske Eliminativism 

References

  1. Allen, C., & Hauser, M. (1993). Communication and cognition: Is information the connection? Philosophy of Science, 2(8), 81–91.Google Scholar
  2. Bartels, A. (2006). Defending the structural concept of representation. Theoria, 55, 7–19.Google Scholar
  3. Bechtel, W. (1998). Representations and cognitive explanations: Assessing the dynamicist’s challenge in cognitive science. Cognitive Science, 22(3), 295–318.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Cavallari, N., Frigato, E., Vallone, D., Fröhlich, N., Lopez-Olmeda, J., Foà, A., et al. (2011). A blind circadian clock in cavefish reveals that opsins mediate peripheral clock photoreception. PLoS Biology, 9(9), e1001142.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Churchland, P., & Churchland, P. (2002). Neural worlds and real worlds. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 3, 903–907.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Clark, A. (2001). Reasons, robots and the extended mind. Mind & Language, 16(2), 121–145.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Clark, A., & Toribio, J. (1994). Doing without representing? Synthese, 101(3), 401–431.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Clayton, N., Yu, K., & Dickinson, A. (2001). Scrub jays (Aphelocoma coerulescens) form integrated memories of the multiple features of caching episodes. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Animal Behavior Processes, 27(1), 17–29.Google Scholar
  9. Craik, K. (1943). The nature of explanation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  10. Cummins, R. (1989). Meaning and mental representation. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  11. Cummins, R. (1994). Interpretational semantics. In S. Stich & T. Warfield (Eds.), Mental representation: A reader (pp. 297–298). Cambridge, MA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  12. Danker, J., & Anderson, J. (2010). The ghosts of brain states past: Remembering reactivates the brain regions engaged during encoding. Psychological Bulletin, 136(1), 87.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Dennett, D. (1981). Brainstorms: Philosophical essays on mind and psychology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  14. Desimone, R. (1991). Face-selective cells in the temporal cortex of monkeys. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 3(1), 1–8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Dretske, F. (1988). Explaining behavior: Reasons in a world of causes. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  16. Eliasmith, C. (2005). A unified approach to building and controlling spiking attractor networks. Neural Computation, 17(6), 1276–1314.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Fodor, J. (1985). Fodor’s guide to mental representation: The intelligent auntie’s vade-mecum. Mind, 94(373), 76–100.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Fodor, J. (1990). A theory of content and other essays. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  19. Gallistel, C. (1990). Representations in animal cognition: An introduction. Cognition, 37(1–2), 1–22.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Gallistel, C. (1998). Symbolic processes in the brain: The case of insect navigation. In D. Osherson, D. Scarborough, L. Gleitman, & D. Sternberg (Eds.), An invitation to cognitive science: Methods, models, and conceptual issues (2nd edn., Vol. 4, pp. 1–52). Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
  21. Gallistel, C., & King, A. (2010). Memory and the computational brain. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
  22. Garzón, F., & Keijzer, F. (2011). Plants: Adaptive behavior, root-brains, and minimal cognition. Adaptive Behavior, 19(3), 155–171.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Garzón, F., & Rodriguez, A. (2009). Where is cognitive science heading? Minds and Machines, 19(3), 301–318.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Godfrey-Smith, P. (2006). Mental representation, naturalism, and teleosemantics. In D. Papineau (Ed.), Teleosemantics: New philosophical essays (pp. 42–68). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  25. Goodman, N. (1968). Languages of art: An approach to a theory of symbols. Indianapolis, IN: Bobbs-Merrill.Google Scholar
  26. Goodspeed, D., Chehab, E., Min-Venditti, A., Braam, J., & Covington, M. (2012). Arabidopsis synchronizes jasmonate-mediated defense with insect circadian behavior. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences o the United States of America, 109(12), 4674–4677.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Grush, R. (2004). The emulation theory of representation: Motor control, imagery, and perception. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 27(3), 377–396.Google Scholar
  28. Grush, R. (2008). Representation reconsidered by William M. Ramsey. Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews. http://ndpr.nd.edu/news/23327-representation-reconsidered/.
  29. Hamada, F., Rosenzweig, M., Kang, K., Pulver, S., Ghezzi, A., Jegla, T., et al. (2008). An internal thermal sensor controlling temperature preference in drosophila. Nature, 454(7201), 217–220.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Hubel, D., & Wiesel, T. (1962). Receptive fields, binocular interaction and functional architecture in the cat’s visual cortex. The Journal of Physiology, 160(1), 106–154.Google Scholar
  31. Isaac, A. (2012). Objective similarity and mental representation. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 1–22.Google Scholar
  32. Johnson-Laird, P. (1983). Mental models: Towards a cognitive science of language, inference, and consciousness. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  33. Kay, S. (1997). PAS, present and future: Clues to the origins of circadian clocks. Science, 276(5313), 753–754.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Kent, C., & Lamberts, K. (2008). The encoding–retrieval relationship: Retrieval as mental simulation. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 12(3), 92–98.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Kirsh, D. (1990). When is information explicitly represented. In P. Hanson (Ed.), Information, language and cognition (pp. 340–365). Vancouver: University of British Columbia Press.Google Scholar
  36. Kosslyn, S., & Thompson, W. (2003). When is early visual cortex activated during visual mental imagery? Psychological Bulletin, 129(5), 723–746.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Krantz, D., Luce, R., Suppes, P., & Tversky, A. (Eds.). (1971). The foundations of measurement. New York: Academic Press.Google Scholar
  38. Lehky, S., & Sejnowski, T. (1988). Network model of shape-from-shading: Neural function arises from both receptive and projective fields. Nature, 333(6172), 452–454.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Lettvin, J., Maturana, H., McCulloch, W., & Pitts, W. (1959). What the frog’s eye tells the frog’s brain. Proceedings of the Institute of Radio Engineers, 47(11), 1940–1951.Google Scholar
  40. Lewis, D. (1971). Analog and digital. Nous, 5(3), 321–327.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Locke, J. (1689 [1975]). An essay concerning human understanding. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  42. Miall, C., & Wolpert, D. (1996). Forward models for physiological motor control. Neural Networks, 9(8), 1265–1279.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Millikan, R. (1984). Language, thought, and other biological categories. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  44. O’Brien, G., & Opie, J. (2001). Connectionist vehicles, structural resemblance, and the phenomenal mind. Communication and Cognition, 34, 1–2.Google Scholar
  45. O’Keefe, J., & Dostrovsky, J. (1971). The hippocampus as a spatial map: Preliminary evidence from unit activity in the freely-moving rat. Brain Research, 34(1), 171–175.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. Palmer, S. (1978). Fundamental aspects of cognitive representation. In E. Rosch & B. Bloom-Lloyd (Eds.), Cognition and categorization (pp. 259–303). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.Google Scholar
  47. Ramsey, W. (2007). Representation reconsidered. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  48. Rao, R., & Ballard, D. (1999). Predictive coding in the visual cortex: A functional interpretation of some extra-classical receptive-field effects. Nature Neuroscience, 2(1), 79–87.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  49. Rumelhart, D., Smolensky, P., Mcclelland, J., & Hinton, G. (1986). Schemata and sequential thought processes in pdp models. In J. McClelland, D. Rumelhart, & the PDP Research Group (Eds.), Parallel distributed processing: Explorations in the microstructure of cognition, Vol. 2: Psychological and biological models, Chap. 14 (pp. 7–57). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  50. Schacter, D., Addis, D., & Buckner, R. (2008). Episodic simulation of future events: Concepts, data, and applications. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 1124, 39–60.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  51. Schwartz, A., & Koller, D. (1986). Diurnal phototropism in solar tracking leaves of Lavatera cretica. Plant Physiology, 80(3), 778–781.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  52. Shagrir, O. (2012). Structural representations and the brain. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 63(3), 519–545.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  53. Shepard, R., & Chipman, S. (1970). Second-order isomorphism of internal representations: Shapes of states. Cognitive Psychology, 1(1), 1–17.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  54. Sprevak, M. (2011). Review of William Ramsey, ‘representation reconsidered’. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62(3), 669–675.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  55. Sterelny, K. (1995). Basic minds. Philosophical Perspectives, 9, 251–270.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  56. Swoyer, C. (1991). Structural representation and surrogative reasoning. Synthese, 87(3), 449.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  57. van Fraassen, B. (2008). Scientific Representation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2013

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyRutgers University of New JerseyNew BrunswickUSA

Personalised recommendations