Synthese

, Volume 190, Issue 17, pp 3651–3669

Does doxastic responsibility entail the ability to believe otherwise?

Article

Abstract

Whether responsibility for actions and omissions requires the ability to do otherwise is an important issue in contemporary philosophy. However, a closely related but distinct issue, namely whether doxastic responsibility requires the ability to believe otherwise, has been largely neglected. This paper fills this remarkable lacuna by providing a defence of the thesis that doxastic responsibility entails the ability to believe otherwise. On the one hand, it is argued that the fact that unavoidability is normally an excuse counts in favour of this thesis. On the other hand, three objections against this thesis are discussed and criticized. First, one might think that what suffices for doxastic responsibility is control over or influence on certain desirable or undesirable properties of beliefs. It is argued that this objection misrepresents the issue under consideration. Second, it may be objected that the thesis is contradicted by our intuitions in doxastic analogues of Frankfurt-style scenarios. It is argued that distinguishing between belief-universals and belief-particulars helps to see why this argument fails. Third and finally, one might draw an analogy with the asymmetry thesis in ethics by arguing that even if blameworthy belief requires the ability to believe otherwise, praiseworthy belief does not. It is argued that the main arguments in favour of this presumed asymmetry are wanting, partly because they fail to distinguish between two different kinds of praiseworthiness. Finally, the author sketches three implications of the thesis that doxastic responsibility entails the ability to believe otherwise: counterfactual construals of responsible belief might be tenable, the deontological conception of epistemic justification needs revision on an important point, and there might be an important asymmetry between beliefs on the one hand and actions and many non-doxastic consequences on the other.

Keywords

Ability to believe otherwise Doxastic responsibility Excuses Frankfurt-style cases 

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Adams R. M. (1985) Involuntary sins. The Philosophical Review 94(1): 3–31CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Alston, W. P. (1989). The deontological conception of epistemic justification. In Epistemic justification: Essays in the theory of knowledge (pp. 115–152). Ithaca/London: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
  3. Bennett J. (1980) Accountability. In: Van Straaten Z. (Ed.), Philosophical subjects: Essays presented to P.F. Strawson. Clarendon Press, Oxford, pp 14–47Google Scholar
  4. Bonjour L. (1985) The structure of empirical knowledge. Harvard University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  5. Booth A. R., Peels R. (2010) Why responsible belief is blameless belief. Journal of Philosophy 107(5): 257–265Google Scholar
  6. Chisholm R. M. (1977) Theory of knowledge. Prentice-Hall, Englewood CliffGoogle Scholar
  7. Clarke M. (1986) Doxastic voluntarism and forced belief. Philosophical Studies 50(1): 39–51CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Clifford, W. K. (1901). The ethics of belief. In Lectures and essays, Vol. II (pp. 163–205). London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
  9. Corlett J. A. (2008) Epistemic responsibility. International Journal of Philosophical Studies 16(2): 179–200CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Dretske F. (2000) Entitlement: Epistemic rights without epistemic duties?. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 60(3): 591–606CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Fischer, J. M. (1985–1986). Responsibility and failure. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 86, 251–270.Google Scholar
  12. Fischer J. M. (1994) The metaphysics of free will: An essay on control. Blackwell Publishers, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  13. Fischer J. M., Ravizza M. (1992) Responsibility, freedom, and reason. Ethics 102(2): 368–389CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Fischer J. M., Ravizza M. (1993) Responsibility for consequences. In: Fischer J. M., Ravizza M. (Eds.), Perspectives on moral responsibility. Cornell University Press, Ithaca, pp 322–347Google Scholar
  15. Fischer J. M., Ravizza M. (1998) Responsibility and control: A theory of moral responsibility. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Frankfurt H. G. (1969) Alternate possibilities and moral responsibility. The Journal of Philosophy 66(23): 829–839CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Frankfurt H. G. (1993) What we are morally responsible for. In: Fischer J. M. , Ravizza M. (Eds.), Perspectives on moral responsibility. Cornell University Press, Ithaca, pp 286–295Google Scholar
  18. Haji I. (2000) Alternate possibilities and responsibility. Journal of Social Philosophy 31(3): 259–267CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Haji I. (2000) Control requirements for moral appraisals: An asymmetry. The Journal of Ethics 4(4): 351–356Google Scholar
  20. Heil J. (1984) Doxastic incontinence. Mind 93: 56–70CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Heller M. (2000) Hobartian voluntarism: Grounding a deontological conception of epistemic justification. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 81: 130–141CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Hetherington S. (2002) Epistemic responsibility: A dilemma. The Monist 85(3): 398–414CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Jäger, C. (2004). Epistemic deontology, doxastic voluntarism, and the principle of alternate possibilities. In W. Löffler & P. Weingartner (Eds.), Knowledge and belief: Proceedings of the 26th international Wittgenstein symposium (pp. 217–227). Vienna: Öbv&hpt Verlagsgesellschaft.Google Scholar
  24. Kim K. (1994) The deontological conception of epistemic justification and doxastic voluntarism. Analysis 54(4): 282–284CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Kornblith H. (1983) Justified belief and epistemically responsible action. Philosophical Review 92(1): 33–48CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Leon M. (2002) Responsible believers. The Monist 85(3): 421–435CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Montmarquet J. A. (1993) Epistemic virtue and doxastic responsibility. Rowman & Littlefield, LanhamGoogle Scholar
  28. Nottelmann N. (2007) Blameworthy belief: A study in epistemic deontologism. Springer, DordrechtGoogle Scholar
  29. Nottelmann, N., & Peels, R. (2013). Some metaphysical implications of a credible ethics of belief. In N. Nottelmann (Ed.), New essays on belief: Structure, constitution, and content (provisional title). New York: Palgrave Macmillan; forthcoming.Google Scholar
  30. Ryan S. (2003) Doxastic compatibilism and the ethics of belief. Philosophical Studies 17(1–2): 47–79CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Smith A. M. (2005) Responsibility for attitudes: Activity and passivity in mental life. Ethics 115(1): 236–271CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Steup M. (1988) The deontic conception of epistemic justification. Philosophical Studies 53(1): 65–84CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Steup M. (2008) Doxastic freedom. Synthese 31(3): 375–392CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Stocker M. (1982) Responsibility especially for beliefs. Mind 91(3): 398–417CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Strawson, P. F. (1974). Freedom and resentment. In Freedom and resentment and other essays (pp. 1–25). London: Methuen & Co.Google Scholar
  36. Van Inwagen P. (1983) An essay on free will. Clarendon Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  37. Wolf S. (1980) Asymmetrical freedom. Journal of Philosophy 77(3): 151–166CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Wolf S. (1990) Freedom within reason. Oxford University Press, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  39. Wolterstorff N. (2005) Obligation, entitlement, and rationality. In: Steup M., Sosa E. (Eds.), Contemporary debates in epistemology. Blackwell Publishing, Malden, pp 326–338Google Scholar
  40. Zagzebski L. (2001) Must knowers be agents?. In: Fairweather A., Zagzebski L. (Eds.), Virtue epistemology: Essays on epistemic virtue and responsibility. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 142–157Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2012

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Philosophy DepartmentVU University AmsterdamAmsterdamThe Netherlands

Personalised recommendations