Synthese

, Volume 190, Issue 5, pp 831–850

Fast and frugal heuristics: rationality and the limits of naturalism

Article

Abstract

Gerd Gigerenzer and Thomas Sturm have recently proposed a modest form of what they describe as a normative, ecological and limited naturalism. The basic move in their argument is to infer that certain heuristics we tend to use should be used in the right ecological setting. To address this argument, we first consider the case of a concrete heuristic called Take the Best (TTB). There are at least two variants of the heuristic which we study by making explicit the choice functions they induce, extending these variants of TTB beyond binary choice. We argue that the naturalistic argument can be applied to only one of the two variants of the heuristic; we also argue that the argument for the extension requires paying attention to other “rational” virtues of heuristics aside from efficacy, speed, and frugality. This notwithstanding, we show that there is a way of extending the right variant of TTB to obtain a very well behaved heuristic that could be used to offer a stronger case for the naturalistic argument (in the sense that if this heuristic is used, it is also a heuristic that we should use). The second part of the article considers attempts to extending the naturalistic argument from algorithms dealing with inference to heuristics dealing with choice. Our focus is the so-called Priority Heuristic, which we extend from risk to uncertainty. In this setting, the naturalist argument seems more difficult to formulate, if it remains feasible at all. Normativity seems in this case extrinsic to the heuristic, whose main virtue seems to be its ability to describe actual patterns of choice. But it seems that a new version of the naturalistic argument used with partial success in the case of inference is unavailable to solve the normative problem of whether we should exhibit the patterns of choice that we actually display.

Keywords

Bounded Rationality Fast and frugal heuristics Priority heuristic Take the best Naturalism Normativity 

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Al-Najjar N. I., Weinstein J. (2009) The ambiguity aversion literature: A critical assessment. Economics and Philosophy 25: 249–284CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Arló-Costa H., Pedersen A. P. (2011a) Bounded rationality: Models for some fast and frugal heuristics. In: Gupta A., van Benthem J. F. A. K., Pacuit E. (eds) Games, norms and reasons: Logic at the crossroads. A tribute to Rohit Parikh on the occasion of his 70th birthday. Springer, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  3. Arló-Costa, H., & Pedersen, A. P. (2011b). Heuristics and maximization: Take the Best extended beyond binary choice. Manuscript, Carnegie Mellon University.Google Scholar
  4. Brandstátter E., Gigerenzer G., Hertwig R. (2006) The priority heuristic: Making choices without trade-offs. Psychological Review 113(2): 409–432CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Gigerenzer G. (2000) Adaptive thinking: Rationality in the real world. Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  6. Gigerenzer G., Goldstein D. G. (1996) Reasoning the fast and frugal way: Models of bounded rationality. Psychological Review 103(4): 650–669CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Gigerenzer, G., Sturm, T. (2012). How (far) can rationality be naturalized? Synthese, 187, 243–268.Google Scholar
  8. Kahneman D., Tversky A. (1979) Prospect theory: An analysis of decision under risk. Econometrica 47(2): 263–292CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Kahneman D., Tversky A. (1992) Advances in prospect theory: Advances in prospect theory: Cumulative representation of uncertainty. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty 5(4): 297–323CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Kitcher P. (1992) The naturalists return. The Philosophical Review 101(1): 53–114CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Leland J. W. (1994) Generalized similarity judgments: An alternative explanation for choice anomalies. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty 9(2): 151–172CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Levi, I. (1967). Gambling with truth: An essay on induction and the aims of science. New York: Alfred A. Knopf.Google Scholar
  13. Quine, W. V. O. (1969). Epistemology naturalized. In Ontological relativity and other essays. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
  14. Rubinstein A. (1988) Similarity and decision-making under risk (is there a utility theory resolution to the allais paradox?). Journal of Economic Theory 46(1): 145–153CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Rubinstein A., Salant Y. (2006) A model of choice from lists. Theoretical Economics 45: 3–17Google Scholar
  16. Salant, Y. (2003). Limited computational resources favor rationality. Discussion Paper 320, Center for the Study of Rationality, Hebrew University of Jerusalem.Google Scholar
  17. Seidenfeld T. (1988) Decision theory without “independence” or without “ordering”: What is the difference?. Economics and Philosophy 4: 267–290CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Wakker P. (2010) Prospect theory: For risk and ambiguity. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeCrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2012

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyCarnegie Mellon UniversityPittsburghUSA

Personalised recommendations