Synthese

, Volume 189, Issue 1, pp 75–96 | Cite as

Against the identification of assertoric content with compositional value

Article

Abstract

This essay investigates whether the things we say are identical to the things our sentences mean. It is argued that these theoretical notions should be distinguished, since assertoric content does not respect the compositionality principle. As a paradigmatic example, Kaplan’s formal language LD is shown to exemplify a failure of compositionality. It is demonstrated that by respecting the theoretical distinction between the objects of assertion and compositional values certain conflicts between compositionality and contextualism are avoided. This includes the conflict between eternalism and the semantics of tense, the embedding problems for contextualism about epistemic modals and taste claims, and the conflict between direct reference and the semantics of bound pronouns (and monstrous operators). After presenting the theoretical picture which distinguishes assertoric content from compositional semantic value, some objections to the picture are addressed. In so doing, the objection from King (Philos Perspect 17(1):195–246, 2003) stemming from apparent complications with the interaction of temporal expressions and attitude reports is assessed and shown to be non-threatening.

Keywords

Assertoric content Compositionality Contextualism Propositions Direct reference Monsters Embedding Semantics 

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Anand, P., & Nevins, A. (2004). Shifty operators in changing contexts. In K. Watanabe & R. Young (Eds.), Proceedings of the 14th conference on semantics and linguistic theory.Google Scholar
  2. Chalmers, D. (2011). Propositions and attitude ascriptions: A Fregean account. Noûs, 45, 595–639.Google Scholar
  3. Cumming S. (2008) Variablism. Philosophical Review 117(4): 605–631CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Dummett M. (1973) Frege: Philosophy of language. Gerald Duckworth, LondonGoogle Scholar
  5. Dummett M. (1991) The logical basis of metaphysics. Harvard University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  6. Egan A. (2007) Epistemic modals, relativism and assertion. Philosophical Studies 133(1): 1–22CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Egan A., Hawthorne J., Weatherson B. (2005) Epistemic modals in context. In: Preyer G., Peter G. (eds) Contextualism in philosophy: Knowledge, meaning, and truth. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 131–170Google Scholar
  8. Evans, G. (1985). Does tense logic rest on a mistake? In Collected papers: Gareth Evans (pp. 343–363). Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  9. Frege G. (1892) Über Sinn und Bedeutung. Zeitschrift für Philosophie und philosophische Kritik 100: 25–50Google Scholar
  10. Heim I., Kratzer A. (1998) Semantics in generative grammar. Blackwell, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  11. Hintikka J. (1969) Semantics for propositional attitudes. In: Davis J., Hockney D., Wilson W. (eds) Philosophical logic. Reidel, Dordrecht, pp 21–45CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Kaplan D. (1989a) Demonstratives. In: Almog J., Perry J., Wettstein H. (eds) Themes from Kaplan. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 481–563Google Scholar
  13. Kaplan D. (1989b) Afterthoughts. In: Almog J., Perry J., Wettstein H. (eds) Themes from Kaplan. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 565–614Google Scholar
  14. King J. (2003) Tense, modality, and semantic values. Philosophical Perspectives 17(1): 195–246CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. King J. (2007) The nature and structure of content. Oxford University Press, OxfordCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Lewis D. (1970) General semantics. Synthese 22(1): 18–67CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Lewis D. (1980) Index, context and content. In: Kanger S., Ohman S. (eds) Philosophy and grammar. Reidel, Amsterdam, pp 79–100CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. MacFarlane J. (2003) Future contingents and relative truth. The Philosophical Quarterly 53(212): 321–336CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Moore G. E. (1927) Facts and propositions. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes 7: 171–206Google Scholar
  20. Ninan, D. (forthcoming). Propositions, semantic values, and rigidity. Philosophical Studies. doi:10.1007/s11098-010-9677-y.
  21. Ninan, D. (2010). Semantics and the objects of assertion. Linguistics and Philosophy, 33(5), 355–380.Google Scholar
  22. Pagin P., Westerståhl D. (2010) Compositionality I: Definitions and variants. Philosophy Compass 5(3): 250–264CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Prior A. (1957) Time and modality. Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  24. Rabern, B. (forthcoming). Monsters in Kaplan’s logic of demonstratives. Philosophical Studies. doi:10.1007/s11098-012-9855-1.
  25. Richard M. (1982) Tense, propositions, and meanings. Philosophical Studies 41(3): 337–351CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Salmon N. (1986) Frege’s puzzle. MIT Press, Cambridge MAGoogle Scholar
  27. Salmon N. (1989) Tense and singular propositions. In: Almog J., Perry J., Wettstein H. (eds) Themes from Kaplan. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 331–392Google Scholar
  28. Salmon, N. (2003). Tense and intension. In A. Jokic & Q. Smith (Eds.), Time, tense, and reference (pp. 109–154). Cambridge: MIT Press. (Reprinted in Salmon (2005), Metaphysics, mathematics, and meaning, Chap. 18. References are to the reprint.)Google Scholar
  29. Salmon N. (2006) A theory of bondage. The Philosophical Review 115(4): 415CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Sauerland, U., & Schenner, M. (2009). Content in embedded sentences. In A. Esposito, A. Hussain, M. Marinaro, & R. Martone (Eds.), Multimodal signals: cognitive and algorithmic issues. Lecture notes in computer science, Vol. 5398 (197–207). Heidelberg: Springer Berlin.Google Scholar
  31. Schaffer J. (2011) Perspective in taste predicates and epistemic modals. In: Weatherson B., Egan A. (eds) Epistemic modality. Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  32. Schaffer, J. (2012). Necessitarian propositions. Synthese. doi:10.1007/s11229-012-0097-8 (this volume).
  33. Schlenker P. (2003) A plea for monsters. Linguistics and Philosophy 26(1): 29–120CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Soames S. (2011) True at. Analysis 71(1): 124–133CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Stalnaker R. (1970) Pragmatics. Synthése 22: 272–289CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Stalnaker R. (1978) Assertion. Syntax and Semantics 9: 315–332Google Scholar
  37. Stanley J. (1997) Rigidity and content. In: Heck R. (eds) Language, thought, and logic: Essays in honor of Michael Dummett. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 131–156Google Scholar
  38. Stanley J. (2000) Context and logical form. Linguistics and Philosophy 23(4): 391–434CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Stanley J. (2002) Modality and what is said. Noûs 36(s16): 321–344CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Weatherson B. (2008) Attitudes and relativism. Philosophical Perspectives 22(1): 527–544CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Weber, C. (2012). Eternalism and propositional multitasking: In defence of the operator argument. Synthese. doi:10.1007/s11229-012-0092-0 (this volume).
  42. Yalcin S. (2007) Epistemic modals. Mind 116(464): 983–1026CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Zimmerman T. E. (1991) Kontextabhängigkeit. In: von Stechow A., Wunderlich D. (eds) Semantik: ein internationales Handbuch der zeitgenössischen Forschung. de Gruyter, Berlin, pp 151–229Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2012

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.The Australian National UniversityCanberraAustralia

Personalised recommendations