Synthese

, Volume 189, Issue 3, pp 483–513

Mirroring versus simulation: on the representational function of simulation

Article

Abstract

Mirror neurons and systems are often appealed to as mechanisms enabling mindreading, i.e., understanding other people’s mental states. Such neural mirroring processes are often treated as instances of mental simulation rather than folk psychological theorizing. I will call into question this assumed connection between mirroring and simulation, arguing that mirroring does not necessarily constitute mental simulation as specified by the simulation theory of mindreading. I begin by more precisely characterizing “mirroring” (Sect. 2) and “simulation” (Sect. 3). Mirroring results in a neural process in an observer that resembles a neural process of the same type in the observed agent. Although simulation is often characterized in terms of resemblance (Goldman, Simulating minds: The philosophy, psychology, and neuroscience of mindreading, 2006), I argue that simulation requires more than mere interpersonal mental resemblance: A simulation must have the purpose or function of resembling its target (Sect. 3.1). Given that mirroring processes are generated automatically, I focus on what is required for a simulation to possess the function of resembling its target. In Sect. 3.2 I argue that this resemblance function, at least in the case of simulation-based mindreading, requires that a simulation serve as a representation or stand-in of what it resembles. With this revised account of simulation in hand, in Sect. 4 I show that the mirroring processes do not necessarily possess the representational function required of simulation. To do so I describe an account of goal attribution involving a motor mirroring process that should not be characterized as interpersonal mental simulation. I end in Sect. 5 by defending the conceptual distinction between mirroring and simulation, and discussing the implications of this argument for the kind of neuroscientific evidence required by simulation theory.

Keywords

Mirror neurons Mirror systems Mirroring Mindreading Simulation theory Cognitive function Neural reuse Representation Resemblance Functional analysis 

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Anderson M. L. (2010) Neural re-use as a fundamental organizational principle of the brain. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 33: 245–313CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Bergeron V. (2007) Anatomical and functional modularity in cognitive science: Shifting the focus. Philosophical Psychology 20(2): 175–195CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Biggs S. (2007) The phenomenal mindreader: A case for phenomenal simulation. Philosophical Psychology 20(1): 29–42CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Biggs S. (2009) Phenomenal concepts in mindreading. Philosophical Psychology 22(6): 647–667CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Blakemore S.-J., Decety J. (2001) From perception of action to the understanding of intention. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 2: 561–567Google Scholar
  6. Blakemore S.-J., Frith C. (2005) The role of motor contagion in the prediction of action. Neuropsychologia 43: 260–267CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Cummins R. (1996) Representations, targets and attitudes. MIT Press, Cambridge, MAGoogle Scholar
  8. Csibra G. (2007) Action mirroring and action interpretation: An alternative account. In: Haggard P., Rosetti Y., Kawato M. (eds) Sensorimotor foundations of higher cognition. Attention and performance XXII. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 427–451Google Scholar
  9. di Pellegrino G., Fadiga L., Fogassi L., Gallese V., Rizzolatti G. (1992) Understanding motor events: A neurophysiological study. Experimental Brain Research 91(1): 176–180CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Etzel J. A., Gazzola V., Keysers C. (2008) Testing simulation theory with cross-modal multivariate classification of fMRI data. PLoS one 3(11): e3690CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Fisher J. (2006) Does simulation theory really involve simulation?. Philosophical Psychology 19(4): 417–432CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Fogassi L., Ferrari P. F., Gesierich B., Rozzi S., Chersi F., Rizzolatti G. (2005) Parietal lobe: From action organization to intention understanding. Science 308: 662–667CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Gallese V. (2001) The “shared manifold” hypothesis. Journal of Consciousness Studies 8(5–7): 33–50Google Scholar
  14. Gallese V., Fadiga L., Fogassi L., Rizzolatti G. (1996) Action recognition in the premotor cortex. Brain 119: 593–609CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Gallese V., Goldman A. (1998) Mirror neurons and the simulation theory of mind-reading. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 2(12): 493–501CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Gallese V., Keysers C., Rizzolatti G. (2004) A unifying view of the basis of social cognition. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 8(9): 396–403CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Gazzola V., Keysers C. (2009) The observation and execution of actions share motor and somatosensory voxels in all tested subjects: Single-subject analyses of unsmoothed fMRI data. Cerebral Cortex 19(6): 1239–1255CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Goldman, A. I. (2005, January 25). Reply to Csibra. Discussion of “Mirror systems, social understanding and social cognition.” Interdisciplines: What do mirror neurons mean? Retrieved March 14, 2011, from http://www.interdisciplines.org/medias/confs/archives/archive_8.pdf.
  19. Goldman A. I. (2006) Simulating minds: The philosophy, psychology, and neuroscience of mindreading. Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  20. Goldman A. I. (2009a) Mirroring, mindreading, and simulation. In: Pineda J. A. (Ed.) Mirror neuron systems. Humana Press, New York, pp 311–330Google Scholar
  21. Goldman A. I. (2009b) Mirroring, simulating and mindreading. Mind and Language 24(2): 235–252CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Goldman A. I. (2009c) Simulation theory and cognitive neuroscience. In: Murphy D., Bishop M. (eds) Stich and his critics. Wiley/Blackwell, Malden, MA, pp 137–151Google Scholar
  23. Goldman, A. I., & Shanton, K. (in press). The case for simulation theory. In A. Leslie & T. German (Eds.), Handbook of “Theory of mind.”. New York: Psychology Press.Google Scholar
  24. Gordon R. (2008) Beyond mindreading. Philosophical Explorations 11(3): 219–222CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Grush R. (1997) The architecture of representation. Philosophical Psychology 10(1): 5–23CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Hurley S. (2008) The shared circuits model: How control, mirroring, and simulation can enable imitation, deliberation, and mindreading. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 31: 1–58CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Iacoboni M. (2008) Mirroring people: The new science of how we connect with others. Farrar Straus and Giroux, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  28. Iacoboni M., Molnar-Szackas I., Gallese V., Buccino G., Mazziotta J. C., Rizzolatti G. (2005) Grasping the intentions of others with one’s own mirror neuron system. PLoS Biology 3(79): 529–535Google Scholar
  29. Jackson P., Meltzoff A., Decety J. (2005) How do we perceive the pain of others? A window into the neural processes involved in empathy. NeuroImage 24: 771–779CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Jacob P. (2009a) The tuning-fork model of human social cognition: A critique. Consciousness and Cognition 18: 229–243CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Jacob P. (2009b) What do mirror neurons contribute to human social cognition?. Mind & Language 23(2): 190–223CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Keysers C., Gazzola V. (2009a) Expanding the mirror: Vicarious activity for actions, emotions, and sensations. Current Opinion in Neurobiology 19: 666–671CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Keysers C., Gazzola V. (2009b) Unifying social cognition. In: Pineda J. A. (Ed.) Mirror neuron systems. Humana Press, New York, pp 3–37Google Scholar
  34. Kilner J. M., Friston K. J., Frith C. D. (2007a) The mirror-neuron system: A Bayesian perspective. NeuroReport 18(6): 619–623CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Kilner J. M., Friston K. J., Frith C. D. (2007b) Predictive coding: An account of the mirror neuron system. Cognitive Processing 8: 159–166CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Millikan R. G. (1989) Biosemantics. Journal of Philosophy 86(6): 281–297CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Mukamel R., Ekstrom A., Kaplan J., Iacoboni M., Fried I. (2010) Single-neuron responses in humans during execution and observation of actions. Current Biology 20: 750–756CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Oberman L. M., Ramachandran V. S. (2007) The simulating social mind: The role of the mirror neuron system and simulation in the social and communicative deficits of autism spectrum disorders. Psychological Bulletin 133(2): 310–327CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. O’Brien G., Opie J. (2004) Notes toward a structuralist theory of mental representation. In: Clapin H., Staines P., Slezak P. (eds) Representation in mind: New approaches to mental representation. Elsevier, Amsterdam, pp 1–20Google Scholar
  40. Oztop E., Wolpert D., Kawato M. (2005) Mental state inference using visual control parameters. Brain Research Cognitive Brain Research 22(2): 129–151CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Palmer S. E. (1978) Fundamental aspects of cognitive representation. In: Rosch E., Lloyd B. B. (eds) Cognition and categorization. Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Hillsdale, NJ, pp 259–303Google Scholar
  42. Pineda J. A. (2009) Action mirroring and action interpretation: An alternative account. In: Pineda J. A. (Ed.) Mirror neuron systems: The role of mirroring processes in social cognition. Humana, New York, pp 5–8Google Scholar
  43. Ramsey W. (2007) Representation reconsidered. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. Ramsey W. (2010) How not to build a hybrid: Simulation vs. fact-finding. Philosophical Psychology 23(6): 775–795CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. Rizzolatti G., Craighero L. (2004) The mirror-neuron system. Annual Review of Neuroscience 27: 169–192CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. Rizzolatti G., Fadiga L., Gallese V., Fogassi L. (1996) Premotor cortex and the recognition of motor actions. Cognitive Brain Research 3: 131–141CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. Rizzolatti G., Fogassi L., Gallese V. (2001) Neurophysiological mechanisms underlying the understanding and imitation of action. Nature Review Neuroscience 2: 661–670CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  48. Rizzolatti G., Fogassi L., Gallese V. (2004) Cortical mechanisms subserving object grasping, action understanding, and imitation. In: Gazzaniga M. (Ed.) The cognitive neurosciences III. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp 427–440Google Scholar
  49. Rizzolatti G., Sinigaglia C. (2008) Mirrors in the brain: How our minds share actions and emotions. Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  50. Rizzolatti G., Sinigaglia C. (2010) The functional role of the parieto-frontal mirror circuit: Interpretations and misinterpretations. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 11(4): 264–274CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  51. Shanton K., Goldman A. (2010) Simulation theory. Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews: Cognitive Science 1(4): 527–538Google Scholar
  52. Shepard R. N., Chipman S. (1970) Second-order isomorphism of internal representations: Shapes of states. Cognitive Psychology 1: 1–17CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  53. Singer T., Seymour B., O’Doherty J., Kaube H., Dolan R., Frith C. (2004) Empathy for pain involves affective but not sensory components of pain. Science 303: 1157–1162CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  54. Stich S., Nichols S. (1997) Cognitive penetrability, rationality, and restricted simulation. Mind and Language 12: 297–326CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  55. Uithol, S., van Rooij, I., Bekkering, H., & Haselager, P. (in press). Understanding motor resonance. Social neuroscience.Google Scholar
  56. Von Eckardt B. (1993) What is cognitive science?. MIT Press, Cambridge, MAGoogle Scholar
  57. Waskan J. (2006) Models and cognition. MIT Press, Cambridge, MAGoogle Scholar
  58. Wicker B., Keysers C., Plailly J., Royet J.-P., Gallese G., Rizzolatti V. (2003) Both of us disgusted in my insula: The common neural basis of seeing and feeling disgust. Neuron 40: 655–664CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2011

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyUniversity of California, San DiegoLa JollaUSA

Personalised recommendations