Springer Nature is making SARS-CoV-2 and COVID-19 research free. View research | View latest news | Sign up for updates

The psychology of reasoning about preferences and unconsequential decisions

Abstract

People can reason about the preferences of other agents, and predict their behavior based on these preferences. Surprisingly, the psychology of reasoning has long neglected this fact, and focused instead on disinterested inferences, of which preferences are neither an input nor an output. This exclusive focus is untenable, though, as there is mounting evidence that reasoners take into account the preferences of others, at the expense of logic when logic and preferences point to different conclusions. This article summarizes the most recent account of how reasoners predict the behavior and attitude of other agents based on conditional rules describing actions and their consequences, and reports new experimental data about which assumptions reasoners retract when their predictions based on preferences turn out to be false.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in to check access.

References

  1. Amgoud L., Bonnefon J. F., Prade H. (2007) The logical handling of threats, rewards, tips, and warnings. Lecture Notes in Artificial Intelligence 4724: 235–246

  2. Beller S., Bender A., Kuhnmunch G. (2005) Understanding conditional promises and threats. Thinking and Reasoning 11: 209–238

  3. Benferhat S., Bonnefon J. F., Da Silva Neves R. M. (2005) An overview of possibilistic handling of default reasoning, with experimental studies. Synthese 146: 53–70

  4. Bex F., Bench-Capon T., Atkinson K. (2009) Did he jump or was he pushed? Abductive practical reasoning. Artificial Intelligence and Law 17: 79–99

  5. Bonnefon J. F. (2009) A theory of utility conditionals: Paralogical reasoning from decision-theoretic leakage. Psychological Review 116: 888–907

  6. Bonnefon J. F., Hilton D. J. (2004) Consequential conditionals: Invited and suppressed inferences from valued outcomes. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition 30: 28–37

  7. Bonnefon J. F., Sloman S. A. (2011) The causal structure of utility conditionals. Manuscript submitted for publication.

  8. Braine M. D. S. (1978) On the relation between the natural logic of reasoning and standard logic. Psychological Review 85: 1–21

  9. Byrne R. M. J. (1989) Suppressing valid inferences with conditionals. Cognition 31: 61–83

  10. Chater N., Crocker M., Pickering M. (1998) The rational analysis of inquiry: The case for parsing. In: Chater N., Oaksford M. (eds) Rational models of cognition.. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 441–468

  11. De Neys W., Schaeken W., d’Ydewalle G. (2003) Inference suppression and semantic memory retrieval: Every counterexample counts. Memory and Cognition 31: 581–595

  12. Dieussaert K., Schaeken W., De Neys W., d’Ydewalle G. (2000) Initial belief state as a predictor of belief revision. Cahiers de Psychologie Cognitive 19: 277–288

  13. Elio R., Pelletier F. J. (1997) Belief change as propositional update. Cognitive Science 21: 419–460

  14. Evans J. S. B. T. (2002) Logic and human reasoning: An assessment of the deduction paradigm. Psychological Bulletin 128: 978–996

  15. Evans J. S. B. T. (2005) The social and communicative function of conditional statements. Mind & Society 4: 97–113

  16. Evans J. S. B. T., Neilens H., Handley S. J., Over D. E. (2008) When can we say ‘if’?. Cognition 108: 100–116

  17. Evans, J. S. B. T., Newstead, S., & Byrne, R. (1993). Human reasoning: The psychology of deduction. Psychology Press.

  18. Ficici, S. G., & Pfeer, A. (2008). Simultaneously modeling humans’ preferences and their beliefs about others’ preferences. In Proceedings of AAMAS’08 (pp. 323–330). Richland, SC: International Foundation for Autonomous Agents and Multiagent Systems.

  19. Harman G. (1986) Change in view: Principles of reasoning. Bradford Book, Cambridge, MA

  20. James W. (1907) Pragmatism—A new name for some old ways of thinking. Longmans Green, & Co, New York

  21. Johnson-Laird P. N., Byrne R. M. J. (1991) Deduction. Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Hillsdale NJ

  22. Johnson-Laird P. N., Girotto V., Legrenzi P. (2004) Reasoning from inconsistency to consistency. Psychological Review 111: 640–661

  23. Legrenzi P., Politzer G., Girotto V. (1996) Contract proposals: A sketch of a grammar. Theory & Psychology 6: 247–265

  24. López-Rousseau A., Ketelaar T. (2004) “If...”: Satisficing algorithms for mapping conditional statements onto social domains. European Journal of Cognitive Psychology 16: 807–823

  25. López-Rousseau A., Ketelaar T. (2006) Juliet: If they do see thee, they will murder thee: A satisficing algorithm for pragmatic conditionals. Mind & Society 5: 71–77

  26. Markovits H., Schmeltzer C. (2007) What makes people revise their beliefs following contradictory anecdotal evidence? The in uence of systemic variability and direct experience. Cognitive Science 31: 535–547

  27. Miller D. T. (1999) The norm of self-interest. American Psychologist 54: 1053–1060

  28. Oaksford M., Chater N. (2003) Optimal data selection: Revision, review and re-evaluation. Psychonomic Bulletin and Review 10: 289–318

  29. Oaksford M., Chater N., Grainger B. (1999) Probabilistic effects in data selection. Thinking and Reasoning 5: 193–243

  30. Ohm E., Thompson V. (2004) Everyday reasoning with inducements and advice. Thinking and Reasoning 10: 241–272

  31. Ohm E., Thompson V. (2006) Conditional probability and pragmatic conditionals: Dissociating truth and effectiveness. Thinking and Reasoning 12: 257–280

  32. Politzer G., Bonnefon J. F. (2006) Two varieties of conditionals and two kinds of defeaters help reveal two fundamental types of reasoning. Mind and Language 21: 484–503

  33. Politzer G., Carles L. (2001) Belief revision and uncertain reasoning. Thinking and Reasoning 7: 217–234

  34. Ratner R. K., Miller D. T. (1998) The disparity between the actual and assumed power of self-interest. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 74: 53–62

  35. Rips L. J. (1983) Cognitive processes in propositional reasoning. Psychological Review 90: 38–71

  36. Smedslund J. (1997) The structure of psychological common sense. Erlbaum, Mahwah, NJ

  37. Stenning K., van Lambalgen M. (2005) Semantic interpretation as computation in nonmonotonic logic: The real meaning of the suppression task. Cognitive Science 29: 919–960

  38. Thompson V. A., Evans J. S. B. T., Handley S. J. (2005) Persuading and dissuading by conditional argument. Journal of Memory and Language 53: 238–257

  39. Wason P. C., Johnson-Laird P. N. (1972) Psychology of reasoning: Structure and content. Batsford, London

Download references

Author information

Correspondence to Jean-François Bonnefon.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and Permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Bonnefon, J., Girotto, V. & Legrenzi, P. The psychology of reasoning about preferences and unconsequential decisions. Synthese 185, 27–41 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-011-9957-x

Download citation

Keywords

  • Reasoning
  • Preferences
  • Belief revision
  • Experiment