Advertisement

Synthese

, Volume 182, Issue 1, pp 39–55 | Cite as

Bogen and Woodward’s data-phenomena distinction, forms of theory-ladenness, and the reliability of data

  • Samuel Schindler
Article

Abstract

Some twenty years ago, Bogen and Woodward challenged one of the fundamental assumptions of the received view, namely the theory-observation dichotomy and argued for the introduction of the further category of scientific phenomena. The latter, Bogen and Woodward stressed, are usually unobservable and inferred from what is indeed observable, namely scientific data. Crucially, Bogen and Woodward claimed that theories predict and explain phenomena, but not data. But then, of course, the thesis of theory-ladenness, which has it that our observations are influenced by the theories we hold, cannot apply. On the basis of two case studies, I want to show that this consequence of Bogen and Woodward’s account is rather unrealistic. More importantly, I also object against Bogen and Woodward’s view that the reliability of data, which constitutes the precondition for data-to-phenomena inferences, can be secured without the theory one seeks to test. The case studies I revisit have figured heavily in the publications of Bogen and Woodward and others: the discovery of weak neutral currents and the discovery of the zebra pattern of magnetic anomalies. I show that, in the latter case, data can be ignored if they appear to be irrelevant from a particular theoretical perspective (TLI) and that, in the former case, the tested theory can be critical for the assessment of the reliability of the data (TLA). I argue that both TLI and TLA are much stronger senses of theory-ladenness than the classical thesis and that neither TLI nor TLA can be accommodated within Bogen and Woodward’s account.

Keywords

Data Phenomena Bogen and Woodward Reliability Theory-ladenness 

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Benvenuti A. et al (1974) Observation of moonless neutrino-induced inelastic interactions. Physical Review Letters 32(14): 800–803CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Bogen J., Woodward J. (1988) Saving the phenomena. Philosophical Review 97: 303–352CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Duhem, P. (1962). The aim and structure of physical theory (trans: Wiener, P.P., Second French edition). Princeton: Princeton U.P.Google Scholar
  4. Galison P. (1983) How the first neutral-current experiments ended. Reviews of Modern Physics 55: 477–509CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Galison P. (1987) How experiments end. University of Chicago Press, ChicagoGoogle Scholar
  6. Glymour B. (2000) Data and phenomena: A distinction reconsidered. Erkenntnis 52(1): 29–37CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Hacking I. (1983) Representing and intervening. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  8. Haidt D. (2004) The discovery of neutral currents. European Physics Journal C 34: 25–31CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Hasert F. J. et al (1973) Observation of neutrino like interactions without muon or electron in the Gargamelle neutrino experiment. Physics Letters B 46: 138–140CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Heidelberger M. (2003) Theory-ladenness and scientific instruments in experimentation. In: Radder H. (eds) The philosophy of scientific experimentation. University of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh, PA, pp 138–151Google Scholar
  11. Kaiser M. (1991) From rocks to graphs: The shaping of phenomena. Synthese 89: 111–133CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Kaiser, M. (1995). The independence of scientific phenomena. In W. Herfel, W. Krajewski, I. Niiniluoto, & R. Wojcicki (Eds.), Theories and models in scientific process. Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of Science and the Humanities (Vol. 44, pp. 179–200). Amsterdam: Rodopi.Google Scholar
  13. Mason, R. (2003). In N. Oreskes & H. LeGrand (Eds.), Plate tectonics: An insider’s history of the modern theory of the earth. Boulder, Colo.: Westview Press.Google Scholar
  14. Mason R. G. (1958) A magnetic survey off the west coast of the United States between latitudes 32° and 36°N. and longitudes 121° and 128°W. Royal Astronomy Society. Geophysical Journal 1: 320–329Google Scholar
  15. Miller A., Bullock W. (1994) Neutral currents and the history of scientific ideas. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 25(6): 895–931CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Lubkin G.B. (1973) CERN and NAL groups claim evidence for neutral currentss. Physics Today 26: 17–19Google Scholar
  17. Perkins D. (1997) Gargamelle and the discovery of neutral currents. In: Hoddeson L. (eds) The rise of the standard model: Particle physics in the 1960s and 1970s. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  18. Pickering A. (1984) Against putting the phenomena first. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 15: 85–114CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Schindler S. (2007) Rehabilitating theory. The refusal of the bottom-up construction of Scientific Phenomena. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science 38(1): 160–184CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Schindler S. (2008) Model, theory and evidence in the discovery of the DNA structure. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 59: 619–658CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Schindler, S. (under review). Real phenomena vs. background noise: The discovery of neutral currents. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics.Google Scholar
  22. Raff A. D. (1961) The magnetism of the ocean floor. Scientific American 205(4): 320–329CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. van Fraassen B. (1980) The scientific image. Clarendon, OxfordCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Woodward J. (1989) Data and phenomena. Synthese 79: 393–472CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Woodward, J. (2000). Data, phenomena, and reliability. Philosophy of Science, Vol. 67, Supplement. Proceedings of the 1998 Biennial Meetings of the Philosophy of Science Association, Part II: Symposia Papers, pp. S163–S179.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2009

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyUniversity of KonstanzKonstanzGermany

Personalised recommendations