Synthese

, Volume 160, Issue 2, pp 285–295 | Cite as

Kripke’s paradox and the Church–Turing thesis

Original Paper

Abstract

Kripke (1982, Wittgenstein on rules and private language. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press) presents a rule-following paradox in terms of what we meant by our past use of “plus”, but the same paradox can be applied to any other term in natural language. Many responses to the paradox concentrate on fixing determinate meaning for “plus”, or for a small class of other natural language terms. This raises a problem: how can these particular responses be generalised to the whole of natural language? In this paper, I propose a solution. I argue that if natural language is computable in a sense defined below, and the Church–Turing thesis is accepted, then this auxiliary problem can be solved.

Keywords

Church–Turing thesis Kripke Computational theory of mind Extended cognition Rule-following 

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Church A. (1941). The calculi of lambda-conversion. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University PressGoogle Scholar
  2. Clark A. (1997). Being there. Cambridge, MA: MIT PressGoogle Scholar
  3. Dreyfus H.L. (1992). What computers still can’t do. Cambridge, MA: MIT PressGoogle Scholar
  4. Fodor J.A. (1990). A theory of content and other essays. Cambridge, MA: MIT PressGoogle Scholar
  5. Ginet C. (1992). The dispositionalist solution to Wittgenstein’s problem about understanding a rule: Answering Kripke’s objections. In: French P.A., Uehling T.E.J., Wettstein H.K.(eds) Midwest studies in philosophy vol. 17. Notre Dame, University of Notre Dame Press, pp. 53–73Google Scholar
  6. Haugeland J. (1981). Semantic engines: An introduction to mind design. In: Haugeland J.(eds) Mind design. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 1–34Google Scholar
  7. Hutchins E. (1995). Cognition in the wild. Cambridge, MA: MIT PressGoogle Scholar
  8. Kripke S.A. (1982). Wittgenstein on rules and private language. Cambridge, MA: MIT PressGoogle Scholar
  9. Maddy P. (1984). How the causal theorist follows a rule. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 9, 457–477Google Scholar
  10. McGinn C. (1984). Wittgenstein on meaning. Oxford, BlackwellGoogle Scholar
  11. Mellor D.H. (1977). Natural kinds. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 28, 299–312CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Miller A., Wright C.(eds) (2002). Rule-following and meaning. Chesham, AcumenGoogle Scholar
  13. Millikan R.G. (1990). Truth rules, hoverflies, and the Kripke–Wittgenstein paradox. Review 99, 323–353Google Scholar
  14. Putnam H. (1975). The meaning of “meaning”. In : Mind, language and reality, philosophical papers vol 2. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, pp. 215–271Google Scholar
  15. Rosch E. (1973). On the internal structure of perceptual and semantic categories. In: Moore T.(eds) Cognitive development and the acquisition of language. New York, Academic PressGoogle Scholar
  16. Searle J.R. (1980). Minds, brains, and programs. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3, 417–424CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Zymach E. (1976). Putnam’s theory of the reference of subject terms. Journal of Philosophy 73, 116–127CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media, Inc. 2006

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.King’s CollegeCambridgeUK

Personalised recommendations