Studia Logica

, Volume 100, Issue 4, pp 855–877

Tolerance and Mixed Consequence in the S’valuationist Setting

  • Pablo Cobreros
  • Paul Egré
  • David Ripley
  • Robert van Rooij
Article

Abstract

In a previous paper (see ‘Tolerant, Classical, Strict’, henceforth TCS) we investigated a semantic framework to deal with the idea that vague predicates are tolerant, namely that small changes do not affect the applicability of a vague predicate even if large changes do. Our approach there rests on two main ideas. First, given a classical extension of a predicate, we can define a strict and a tolerant extension depending on an indifference relation associated to that predicate. Second, we can use these notions of satisfaction to define mixed consequence relations that capture non-transitive tolerant reasoning. Although we gave some empirical motivation for the use of strict and tolerant extensions, making use of them commits us to the view that sentences of the form ‘\({p {\vee} {\neg} p}\)’ and ‘\({p {\wedge} {\neg} p}\)’ are not automatically valid or unsatisfiable, respectively. Some philosophers might take this commitment as a negative outcome of our previous proposal. We think, however, that the general ideas underlying our previous approach to vagueness can be implemented in a variety of ways. This paper explores the possibility of defining mixed notions of consequence in the more classical super/sub-valuationist setting and examines to what extent any of these notions captures non-transitive tolerant reasoning.

Keywords

Vagueness Tolerance Logical Consequence Super- and Sub-valuationism 

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. 1.
    Alxatib, S., and J. Pelletier, The psychology of vagueness: Borderline cases and contradictions, Mind and Language, (Forthcoming).Google Scholar
  2. 2.
    Arruda, A., Aspects of the historical development of paraconsistent logic, in Priest, Routley and Norman (eds.), Paraconsistent logic: essays on the inconsistent, Munchen: Philosophia, 1989.Google Scholar
  3. 3.
    Bennett, B., Modal semantics for knowledge bases dealing with vague concepts, in A. G. Cohn, L. Schubert and S. Shapiro (eds.), Principles of Knowledge Representation and Reasoning: Proceedings of the 6th International Conference (KR-98), Morgan Kaufman, 1998.Google Scholar
  4. 4.
    Béziau, J.-Y., Transitivity and paradoxes, in J. Skilters (ed.), The Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication, University of Riga, 2006, pp. 207–211.Google Scholar
  5. 5.
    Cobreros P., Egré P., Ripley D., van Rooij R.: Tolerant, classical, strict. Journal of Philosophical Logic 41, 347–385 (2012)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. 6.
    Dalrymple M., Kanazawa M., Kim Y., Mchombo S., Peters S.: Reciprocal expressions and the concept of reciprocity. Linguistics and Philosophy 21, 159–210 (1998)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. 7.
    Dietz, R., Vagueness and indeterminacy, in L. Horsten and R. Pettigrew (eds.), The Continuum Companion to Philosophical Logic, Oxford University Press, 2011.Google Scholar
  8. 8.
    Fine K.: Vagueness, truth and logic. Synthese 30, 265–300 (1975)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. 9.
    Hyde D.: From heaps and gaps to heaps of gluts. Mind 106(424), 641–660 (1997)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. 10.
    Hyde D.: Vagueness, Logic and Ontology. Aldershot, Ashgate (2008)Google Scholar
  11. 11.
    Kamp, H., Two theories about adjectives, in E. L. Keenan (ed.), Formal semantics of natural language, Cambridge University Press, 1975, pp. 123–155.Google Scholar
  12. 12.
    Kamp H., Partee B.: Prototype theory and compositionality. Cognition 57, 129–191 (1995)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. 13.
    Keefe, R., Theories of Vagueness, Cambridge University Press, 2000.Google Scholar
  14. 14.
    Kremer P., Kremer M.: Some supervaluation-based consequence relations. Journal of Philosophical Logic 32, 225–244 (2003)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. 15.
    Nait-Abdallah, A., The logic of partial information, Springer, 1995.Google Scholar
  16. 16.
    Priest, G., An Introduction to Non-Classical Logic: From If to Is, Cambridge University Press, 2008.Google Scholar
  17. 17.
    Ripley, D., Contradictions at the borders, in R. Nouwen, R. van Rooij, U. Sauerland, and H.-Ch. Smith (eds.), Vagueness in Communication, Springer, 2011, pp. 169–188.Google Scholar
  18. 18.
    Ripley, D., Sorting out the sorites, in F. Berto, E. Mares, and K. Tanaka (eds.), Paraconsistency: Logic and Applications, Springer, (Forthcoming).Google Scholar
  19. 19.
    Rooij, R. van, Vagueness, tolerance and non-transitive entailment, in P. Cintula, C. Fermüller, L. Godo, and P. Hajek (eds.), Reasoning Under Vagueness: Logical, Philosophical and Linguistic Perspectives, College Publications, 2011.Google Scholar
  20. 20.
    Serchuk, P., I. Hargreaves, and R. Zach, Vagueness, logic and use: Four experimental studies on vagueness, Mind and Language, (Forthcoming).Google Scholar
  21. 21.
    Zardini E.: A model of tolerance. Studia Logica 90, 337–368 (2008)CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2012

Authors and Affiliations

  • Pablo Cobreros
    • 1
  • Paul Egré
    • 2
  • David Ripley
    • 3
  • Robert van Rooij
    • 4
  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyUniversity of NavarraPamplonaSpain
  2. 2.Département d’Etudes Cognitives de l’ENSInstitut Jean-Nicod (CNRS-EHESS-ENS)ParisFrance
  3. 3.Department of Philosophy – Old QuadUniversity of MelbourneMelbourneAustralia
  4. 4.Institute for Logic, Language and ComputationUniversiteit van AmsterdamAmsterdamThe Netherlands

Personalised recommendations