Advertisement

Studies in Philosophy and Education

, Volume 30, Issue 6, pp 601–613 | Cite as

The Concept of Profound Boredom: Learning from Moments of Vision

  • Paul GibbsEmail author
Article

Abstract

This paper recognizes that we become bored in our post-modern, consumerist Western world and that boredom is related to this existence and hidden within it. Through Heidegger, it seeks to provide a way to structure our understanding of boredom and suggest ways of acknowledging its cause, and then to allow it to liberate our authentic appreciation of the world of our workplace and what can be learnt through it. Using the approach of focusing on being in a societal workplace environment, and the link to Heidegger’s notion of mood, revealed in Being and Time, boredom’s fundamental role is shown as a complex temporal manifold. Our superficial attempts to deal with things in datable time means that we miss the essential importance of the temporal manifold through which our being is revealed and where the Augenblick, (moment of vision) is the authentic present and temporalises itself of the authentic future (Heidegger in Being and time (trans: J. Macquarrie and E. Robinson). Blackwell, Oxford, 1962, p. 338). For Heidegger this is to be understood as ecstasis (ibid, p. 338) when the resolute Dasein “is carried away to whatever possibilities and circumstances are encountered (ibid, p. 338). Such resoluteness enables the private capabilities to arise in public practice, not, however, in the conformity of what ‘one does’ (Das Man) but as an authentically choosing being. The challenge of an ontological pedagogy, regardless of its place of revelation that this prescribes a possibly be edifying mission for Dasein. Instead of chasing away boredom through busyness, a moment of vision could produce creative and authentic ways of being.

Keywords

Profound boredom Moment of vision Learning Heidegger 

References

  1. Belton, T., & Priyadharshini, E. (2007). Boredom and schooling: a cross-disciplinary exploration. Cambridge Journal of Education, 27(4), 579–595.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Benjamin, W. (2002). The Arcades project. Cambridge: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  3. Biceaga, V. (2006). Temporality and boredom. Continental Philosophy Review, 39(2), 135–153.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Blattner, W. (2006). Heidegger’s being and time. London: Continuum International Publishing Group.Google Scholar
  5. Boss, M. (2009). Metaphysic and the mood of deep boredom. In B. Dalle Pezze (Ed.), Essays on boredom and modernity (pp. 85–109). Amsterdam: Rodopi.Google Scholar
  6. Breidenstein, G. (2007). The meaning of boredom in school lessons. Participant observation in the seventh and eighth form. Ethnography and Education, 2(1), 93–108.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Brogan, W. A. (2005). Heidegger and Aristotle: The two foldness of being. New York: SUNY.Google Scholar
  8. Dreyfus, H. (1992). Being-in-the-world. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  9. Dreyfus, H. (2004). What could be more intelligible than everyday intelligibility? Reinterpreting division I of being and time in the light of division II. Bulletin of Science Technology Society, 24(3), 265–274.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Gibbs, P. (2009). Adopting consumer time: potential issues for higher education. London Review of Education, 7(2), 113–124.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Goodstein, E. S. (2005). Experience without qualities: boredom and modernity. Stanford: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
  12. Heidegger, M. (1962). Being and time (trans: J. Macquarrie & E. Robinson). Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  13. Heidegger, M. (1995). The fundamental concepts of metaphysics, world, finitude, solicitude (trans. W. McNeill & N. Walker). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
  14. Heidegger, M. (1995a). Aristotle’s metaphysics, Vols. 13: on the essence and actuality of Force (Trans. W. Brogan & P. Warnek). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
  15. Heidegger, M. (2007a). What is metaphysics? In W. McNeill (Ed.), Martin Heidegger pathways (pp. 82–96). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  16. Heidegger, M. (2007). Plato’s Doctrine of truth (trans. T. Sheehan) In: Pathmarks (Texts in German Philosophy). ed. W. McNeill. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  17. Husserl, E. (2008). On the phenomenology of the consciousness of internal time (1893–1917). Amsterdam: Springer Publishing.Google Scholar
  18. Kant, I. (2001). Lectures on ethics (trans. P. Heath). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  19. Kierkegaard, S. (2004). Either/or: a fragment of life (trans. A. Hannay). London: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
  20. Mann, S., & Robinson, A. (2009). Boredom in the lecture theatre: an investigation into the contributors, moderators and outcomes of boredom amongst university students. British Educational Research Journal, 35(2), 243–258.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Mansikka, J.-E. (2009). Can boredom educate us? Tracing a mood in Heidegger’s fundamental ontology from an educational point of view. Studies in Philosophy of Education, 28, 255–268.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. McDonald, W. (2009). Kierkegaard’s demonic boredom. In B. Dalle Pezze (Ed.), Essays on boredom and modernity (pp. 61–85). Amsterdam: Rodop BV.I.Google Scholar
  23. McNeill, W. (1999). The glance of the eye, Heidegger, Aristotle, and the ends of theory. Albany: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
  24. Mei, T. S. (2009). Heidegger, work and being. London: Continuum Studies.Google Scholar
  25. Pezze, B. D., & Salzani, C. (2009). Essays on boredom and modernity. Amsterdam: Rodopi B.V.Google Scholar
  26. Rorty, R. (1979). Philosophy and the mirror of nature. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  27. Rorty, R. (1999). Education as socialization and as individualization. In R. Rorty (Ed.), Philosophy and social hope (pp. 114–127). London: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
  28. Simmel, G. (1991). Schopenhauer and Nietzsche; their place in cultural history. In: Schopenhauer and Nietzsche (trans: H. Loiskandl, D. Weinstein & M. Weinstein, pp. 3–12). Illinois: University of Illinois Press.Google Scholar
  29. Stafford, S. P., & Gregory, W. T. (2006). Heidegger’s phenomenology of boredom, and the scientific investigation of conscious experience. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 5, 155–169.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Svendsen, L. (2005). A philosophy of boredom. London: Reaktion Books.Google Scholar
  31. Thompson, I. (2005). Heidegger on Ontotheology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Witt, C. (2003). Ways of being. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
  33. Zimmerman, M. E. (1993). Heidegger, Buddhism and deep ecology. In C. Guignon (Ed.), The Cambridge companion to Heidegger (pp. 240–269). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2011

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Institute for Work Based StudiesUniversity of MiddlesexLondonUK

Personalised recommendations