Advertisement

Studies in Philosophy and Education

, Volume 28, Issue 3, pp 269–281 | Cite as

Educating Political Adversaries: Chantal Mouffe and Radical Democratic Citizenship Education

  • Claudia W. Ruitenberg
Article

Abstract

Many scholars in the area of citizenship education take deliberative approaches to democracy, especially as put forward by John Rawls, as their point of departure. From there, they explore how students’ capacity for political and/or moral reasoning can be fostered. Recent work by political theorist Chantal Mouffe, however, questions some of the central tenets of deliberative conceptions of democracy. In the paper I first explain the central differences between Mouffe’s and Rawls’s conceptions of democracy and politics. To this end I take Eamonn Callan’s Creating Citizens as an example of Rawlsian political education and focus on the role of conflict and disagreement in his account. I then address three areas in which political education would need to change if it were to accept Mouffe’s critiques of deliberative approaches to democracy and her proposal for an agonistic public sphere. The first area is the education of political emotions; the second is fostering an understanding of the difference between the moral and the political; the third is developing an awareness of the historical and contemporary political projects of the “left” and “right.” I propose that a radical democratic citizenship education would be an education of political adversaries.

Keywords

Democracy Citizenship education Agonistics Chantal Mouffe Eamonn Callan 

References

  1. Boler, M. (1999). Feeling power: Emotions and education. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
  2. Callan, E. (1997). Creating citizens: Political education and liberal democracy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  3. Carnegie Corporation of New York. (2003). The civic mission of schools. New York: Carnegie Corporation of New York and CIRCLE.Google Scholar
  4. Freire, P. (2001). Reading the world and reading the word: An interview with Paulo Freire. In W. Hare & J. P. Portelli (Eds.), Philosophy of education: Introductory readings (3rd ed., pp. 145–152). Calgary, AB: Detselig Enterprises (Reprinted from Language Arts, 1985).Google Scholar
  5. Johnston, J. S. (2005). Rawls Kantian educational theory. Educational Theory, 55(2), 201–218.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Koziak, B. (1999). Homeric thumos: The early history of gender, emotion, and politics. The Journal of Politics, 61(4), 1068–1091.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Laclau, E., & Mouffe, C. (1985). Hegemony and socialist strategy: Towards a radical democratic politics (W. Moore & P. Cammack, Trans.). London: Verso.Google Scholar
  8. Macedo, S. (1995). Liberal civic education and religious fundamentalism: The case of God vs. John Rawls. Ethics, 105(3), 468–496.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Milan, A. (2005). Willing to participate: Political engagement of young adults. Canadian Social Trends, 79, 2–7.Google Scholar
  10. Mouffe, C. (2000a). The democratic paradox. London: Verso.Google Scholar
  11. Mouffe, C. (2000b). Deliberative democracy or agonistic pluralism. Political Science Series, 72, 1–17.Google Scholar
  12. Mouffe, C. (2005a). On the political. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
  13. Mouffe, C. (2005b). Some reflections on an agonistic approach to the public. In B. Latour & P. Weibel (Eds.), Making things public: Atmospheres of democracy (pp. 804–807). Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
  14. Mouffe, C. (2005c). The limits of John Rawls’s pluralism. Politics, Philosophy & Economics, 4(2), 221–231.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Norris, P. (2000). A virtuous circle: Political communications in post-industrial societies. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  16. Rancière, J. (2006). Hatred of democracy (S. Corcoran, Trans.). London: Verso.Google Scholar
  17. Rawls, J. (1980). Kantian constructivism in moral theory. The Journal of Philosophy, 77(9), 515–572.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Rawls, J. (1985). Justice as fairness: Political not metaphysical. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 14(3), 223–251.Google Scholar
  19. Rawls, J. (1993). Political liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
  20. Roker, D., Player, K., & Coleman, J. (1999). Young people’s voluntary and campaigning activities as sources of political education. Oxford Review of Education, 25(1/2), 185–198.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Strike, K. A. (1994). On the construction of public speech: Pluralism and public reason. Educational Theory, 44(1), 1–26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2008

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of Educational StudiesUniversity of British ColumbiaVancouverCanada

Personalised recommendations