Advertisement

Social Justice Research

, Volume 21, Issue 2, pp 119–137 | Cite as

On Justifying Punishment: The Discrepancy Between Words and Actions

  • Kevin M. Carlsmith
Article

Abstract

This article reveals a discrepancy between the actual and stated motives for punishment. Two studies conducted with nationally representative samples reveal that people support laws designed on the utilitarian principle of deterrence in the abstract, yet reject the consequences of the same when they are applied. Study 1 (N = 133) found that participants assigned punishment to criminals in a manner consistent with a retributive theory of justice rather than deterrence. The verbal justifications for punishment given by these same respondents, however, failed to correlate with their actual retributive behavior. Study 2 (N = 125) again found that people have favorable attitudes towards utilitarian laws and rate them as “fair” in the abstract, but frequently reject them when they are instantiated in ways that support utilitarian theories. These studies reveal people’s inability to know their own motivations, and show that one consequence of this ignorance is to generate support for laws that they ultimately find unjust.

Keywords

Punishment motives Retributive justice Deterrence Justice Self-knowledge 

Notes

Acknowledgement

I express appreciation to Jennifer Simester who collected data for a pilot version of Study 1, and who provided helpful comments on an earlier draft of this manuscript. Portions of this research were conducted while the author was on leave at Old Dominion University in Norfolk, VA.

References

  1. Bentham, J. (1962). Principles of penal law. In J. Bowring (Ed.), The works of Jeremy Bentham (p. 396). Edinburgh: W. Tait. (Original work published 1843).Google Scholar
  2. Carlsmith, K. M. (2006). The roles of retribution and utility in determining punishment. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 42, 437–451.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Carlsmith, K. M., & Darley, J. M. (2008). Psychological aspects of retributive justice. In M. P. Zanna (Ed.), Advances in experimental social psychology (Vol. 40, pp. 193–236). San Diego, CA: Elsevier.Google Scholar
  4. Carlsmith, K. M., Darley, J. M., & Robinson, P. H. (2002). Why do we punish? Deterrence and just deserts as motives for punishment. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 83, 284–299.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Carlsmith, K. M., Potocki, A., & West, M. (2006). Shifting theories of punishment as a mechanism of bias expression. Paper presented at the Justice Preconference of the SPSP Annual Meeting.Google Scholar
  6. Carlsmith, K. M., Wilson, T. D., & Gilbert, D. (under review). Best served cold: The unexpected consequences of revenge. Colgate University.Google Scholar
  7. Clements, C., Wasieleski, D. T., Chaplin, W. F., Kruh, I. P., & Brown, K. P. (1998). The sentencing goals inventory: Development and validation. Poster session presented at the biennial meeting of the American Psychology-Law Society, Redondo Beach, CA.Google Scholar
  8. Cooksey, R. W. (1996). Judgment analysis: Theory, methods, and applications. San Diego: Academic Press.Google Scholar
  9. Darley, J. M., Carlsmith, K. M., & Robinson, P. H. (2000). Incapacitation and just deserts as motives for punishment. Law and Human Behavior, 24, 659–683.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Darley, J. M., Carlsmith, K. M., & Robinson, P. H. (2001). The ex ante function of the criminal law. Law & Society Review, 35, 701–726.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Ellsworth, P. C., & Ross, L. (1983). Public opinion and capital punishment: A close examination of the views of abolitionists and retentionists. Crime and Delinquency, 29, 116–169.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Ezorsky, G. (1972). Philosophical perspectives on punishment. Albany: SUNY Press.Google Scholar
  13. Feather, N. T., & Souter, J. (2002). Reactions to mandatory sentences in relation to the ethnic identity and criminal history of the offender. Law and Human Behavior, 26, 417–438.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Glaeser, E. L., & Sacerdote, B. (2000). The determinants of punishment: Deterrence, incapacitation, and vengeance. NBER working paper no. 7676.Google Scholar
  15. Grice, H. P. (1975). Logic and conversation. In D. Davidson & G. Harman (Eds.), The logic of grammar. (pp. 64–75). Encino: Dickenson.Google Scholar
  16. Haidt, J. (2001). The emotional dog and its rational tail: A social intuitionist approach to moral judgment. Psychological Review, 108, 814–834.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Hamilton, L. V., & Rytina, S. (1980). Social consensus on norms of justice: Should the punishment fit the crime? American Journal of Sociology, 85, 1117–1144.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Kahneman, D., Schkade, D., & Sunstein, C. R. (1998). Shared outrage and erratic awards: The psychology of punitive damages. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 16, 49–86.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Kant, I. (1952). The science of right. (W. Hastie, Trans.). In R. Hutchins (Ed.), Great books of the western world (pp. 397–446). Edinburgh: T. & T. Clark. (Original work published 1790).Google Scholar
  20. Kunda, Z., & Sherman-Williams, B. (1993). Stereotypes and the construal of individuating information. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 19, 90–99.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Lockyer V. Andrade, 538 U.S. 63 (2003).Google Scholar
  22. McFatter, R. M. (1982). Purposes of punishment: Effects of utilities of criminal sanctions on perceived appropriateness. Journal of Applied Psychology, 67, 255–267.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. McKee, I., & Feather, N. T. (2006, August). Sentencing goals, human values and punitive personality types: The role of revenge in attitudes towards punishment and rehabilitation. Symposium on “Legal Justice.” 11th biennial meeting of the International Society for Justice Research, Berlin, Germany.Google Scholar
  24. Mill, J. S. (1998) Utilitarianism. In R. Crisp (Ed.) J. S. Mill/Utilitarianism. Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Original work published 1871).Google Scholar
  25. Nisbett, R. E., & Wilson, T. D. (1977). Telling more than we can know: Verbal reports on mental processes. Psychological Review, 84, 231–259.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Rachels J. (1986). The elements of moral philosophy. New York: Random House.Google Scholar
  27. Roberts, J. V., & Gebotys, R. J. (1989). The purposes of sentencing: Public support of competing aims. Behavioral Sciences and the Law, 7, 387–402.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Robinson, P. H., & Darley, J. M. (1997). The utility of desert. Northwestern University Law Review, 91, 453–499.Google Scholar
  29. Schroeder, D. A., Steel, J. E., Woodell, A. J., & Bembenek, A. F. (2003). Justice within social dilemmas. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 7, 374–387.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Stanton, J. M., & Weiss, E. M. (2002). Online Panels for Social Science Research: An Introduction to The Study Response Project. (Tech. Rep. No. 13001). Syracuse: Syracuse University, School of Information Studies.Google Scholar
  31. Sunstein, C. R. (2003). On the psychology of punishment. Supreme Court Economic Review, 11, 171–188.Google Scholar
  32. Tyler T. R., & Huo, Y. J. (2002). Trust in the law: Encouraging public cooperation with the police and courts. NY: Russell Sage Foundation.Google Scholar
  33. Van Prooijen, J.-W. (2006). Retributive reactions to suspected offenders: The importance of social categorizations and guilt probability. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 32, 715–726.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Wilson, T. D. (2002). Strangers to ourselves: Discovering the adaptive unconscious. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  35. Wilson, T. D., Hodges, S. D., & LaFleur, S. J. (1995). Effects of introspecting about reasons: Inferring attitudes from accessible thoughts. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 69, 16–28.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Zirkel, P. A. (1997). Courtside: The Midol case. Phi Delta Kappan, 78, 803–804.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media, LLC 2008

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PsychologyColgate UniversityHamiltonUSA

Personalised recommendations