Advertisement

Science & Education

, Volume 27, Issue 9–10, pp 831–861 | Cite as

Towards a Philosophically Guided Schema for Studying Scientific Explanation in Science Education

  • Sahar Alameh
  • Fouad Abd-El-Khalick
Article
  • 68 Downloads

Abstract

Stemming from the realization of the importance of the role of explanation in the science classroom, the Next Generation Science Standards (NGSS Lead States 2013) call for appropriately supporting students to learn science, argue from evidence, and provide explanations. Despite the ongoing emphasis on explanations in the science classroom, there seems to be no well-articulated framework that supports students in constructing adequate scientific explanations, or that helps teachers assess student explanations. Our motivation for this article is twofold: First, we think that the ways in which researchers in science education have studied scientific explanation are, at best, leaves much to be desired and, at worst, simply incomplete. Second, we believe that research about the teaching and learning of explanation in science classrooms must be guided by explicit models or frameworks that specify elements involved in constructing explanations particularly applicable to science. More importantly, we think that the development of such models or guidelines should be based on theoretical and philosophical foundations. In order to develop these frameworks or guidelines, we first outline and clarify models of scientific explanation developed by philosophers of science over the last few decades. In the second section of this article, we present a more recent philosophical work on scientific explanation, the pragmatic approach to studying scientific explanations. This approach suggests a toolbox for analyzing scientists’ scientific explanations, which provides a useful instrument to science education. In Section 3, we discuss the ways by which the previous two sections are useful in developing a K-12 scientific explanation schema. Implications for future research on students’ explanations are discussed.

Keywords

Scientific explanation Nature of science Science education Philosophy of science 

Notes

Compliance with Ethical Standards

Conflict of Interest

The authors certify that they have NO affiliations with or involvement in any organization or entity with any financial or non-financial interest in the subject matter or materials discussed in this manuscript.

References

  1. Achinstein, P. (1984). The pragmatic character of explanation. In P. Asquith & P. Kitcher (Eds.), Philosophy of science (pp. 275–292). East Lansing.Google Scholar
  2. Beebee, H., Hitchcock, C., & Menzies, P. (Eds.). (2009). The Oxford handbook of causation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  3. Braaten, M., & Windschitl, M. (2010). Working toward a stronger conceptualization of scientific explanation for science education. Science Education, 95, 639–669.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Brewer, W. F., Chinn, C. A., & Samarapungavan, A. (2000). Explanation in scientists and children. In F. C. Keil & R. A. Wilson (Eds.), Explanation and cognition. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  5. Cartwright, N. (1983). How the laws of physics lie. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Craver, C. F. (2007). Explanation and causal relevance. In C. F. Craver (Ed.), Explaining the brain: mechanisms and the mosaic unity of neuroscience (pp. 21–62). Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. de Regt, H., Leonelli, S. & Eigner, K. (2009). Scientific understanding: Philosophical perspectives, Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh PressGoogle Scholar
  8. Delen, I., & Krajcik, J. (2018). Synergy and students’ explanations: exploring the role of generic and content-specific scaffolds. International Journal of Science and Mathematics Education, 16(1), 1–21.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Feigl, H. (1970). The ‘orthodox’ view of theories: remarks in defense as well as critique. In M. Radner & S. Winokur (Eds.), Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
  10. Friedman, M. (1974). Explanation and scientific understanding. Journal of Philosophy, 71, 5–19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Gardiner, P. (1959). The nature of historical explanation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  12. Glennan, S. (2002). Rethinking mechanistic explanation. Philosophy of Science, 69, 342–353.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Hausman, D. M. (1998). Causal asymmetries. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Hempel, C. (1965). Aspects of scientific explanation. In C. Hempel (Ed.), Aspects of scientific explanation, and other essays in the philosophy of science (pp. 331–489). New York: Free Press.Google Scholar
  15. Hempel, C. (2001). Deductive nomological vs. statistical explanation. In C. Hempel & J. Fetzer (Eds.), The philosophy of Carl G. Hempel studies in science, explanation, and rationality (pp. 98–169). New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  16. Hempel, C. (2002). Two models of scientific explanation. In Y. Balashov (Ed.), Philosophy of science: contemporary readings (pp. 45–55). London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  17. Hempel, C. G. (1962). Explanation in science and history. In R. Colodny (ed.), Frontiers of Science and Philosophy. University of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh, PA, pp. 36–54.Google Scholar
  18. Hempel, C., & Oppenheim, P. (1948). Studies in the logic of explanation. Philosophy of Science, 15, 135–175.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Hogan, K., & Maglienti, M. (2001). Comparing the epistemological underpinnings of students’ and scientists’ reasoning about conclusions. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 38, 663–687.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Humphreys, P. (1989). Scientific explanation: the causes, some of the causes, and nothing but the causes. In P. Kitcher & W. C. Salmon (Eds.), Scientific explanation (pp. 282–306). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
  21. Kampourakis, K., Silveira, P., & Strasser, B. J. (2016). How do preservice biology teachers explain the origin of biological traits?: a philosophical analysis. Science Education, 100, 1124–1149.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Kitcher, P. (1981). Explanatory unification. Philosophy of Science, 48, 507–531.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Kitcher, P. (1989). Explanatory unification and the causal structure of the world. In P. Kitcher & W. C. Salmon (Eds.), Scientific explanation (pp. 410–499). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
  24. Kitcher, P. (1997). Explanatory unification. In D. Rothbart (Ed.), Science, reason, and reality: Issues in the philosophy of science (pp. 167–186). Fort Worth: Harcourt Brace.Google Scholar
  25. Metz, K. (1991). Development of explanation: incremental and fundamental change in children’s physics knowledge. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 28, 785–797.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Nagel, E. (1961). The structure of science: problems in the logic of scientific explanation. New York: Harcourt, Brace and World.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. National Research Council. (2012). A Framework for K-12 Science Education: Practices, Crosscutting Concepts, and Core Ideas. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press.  https://doi.org/10.17226/13165.Google Scholar
  28. NGSS Lead States. (2013). Next Generation Science Standards: For States, By States. Retrieved from http://www.nextgenscience.org/.
  29. Parnafes, O. (2012). Developing explanations and developing understanding: students explain the phases of the moon using visual representations. Cognition and Instruction, 30, 359–403.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Peker, D., & Wallace, C. S. (2011). Characterizing high school students’ written explanations in biology laboratories. Research in Science Education, 41, 169–191.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Popper, K. (1959). The logic of scientific discovery. London: Hutchinson.Google Scholar
  32. Railton, P. (1978). A deductive-nomological model of probabilistic explanation. Philosophy of Science, 45, 206–226.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Salmon, W. C. (1971). Statistical explanation and statistical relevance. Princeton: University of Pittsburgh Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Salmon, W. C. (1984). Scientific explanation and the causal structure of the world. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  35. Salmon, W. (1989). Four decades of scientific explanation. In P. Kitcher & W. C. Salmon (Eds.), Scientific explanation (pp. 3–219). Minnesota: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
  36. Salmon, W. C. (1998). Causality and explanation. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Scriven, M. (1958). Definitions, explanations, and theories. In H. Feigl, G. Maxwell, & M. Scriven (Eds.), Concepts, theories, and the mind-body problem (pp. 99–195). Minnesota: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
  38. Skipper, R. (1999). Selection and the Extent of Explanatory Unification. Philosophy of Science (Suppl.), 66, S196–209.Google Scholar
  39. Van Fraassen, B. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Weber, E., & Van Bouwel, J. (2009). Causation, unification, and the adequacy of explanations of facts. THEORIA. Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia, 24, 301–320.Google Scholar
  41. Weber, E., Van Bouwel, J., & De Vreese, L. (2013). Scientific explanation. New York: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Weinberg, R. (1985). The molecules of life. Scientific American, 253, 48–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen: a theory of causal explanation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  44. Woody, A. I. (2013). How is the ideal gas law explanatory? Science & Education, 22, 1563–1580.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. Yang, H. T., & Wang, K. H. (2014). A teaching model for scaffolding 4th grade students’ scientific explanation writing. Research in Science Education, 44(4), 531–548.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature B.V. 2018

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.University of Illinois at Urbana ChampaignChampaignUSA
  2. 2.School of EducationThe University of North Carolina at Chapel HillChapel HillUSA

Personalised recommendations