Advertisement

Science & Education

, Volume 24, Issue 1–2, pp 77–99 | Cite as

How Many Times Can You Be Wrong and Still Be Right? T. H. Morgan, Evolution, Chromosomes and the Origins of Modern Genetics

  • Garland E. AllenEmail author
Article

Abstract

Science textbooks and classes mostly emphasize what are considered by today’s standards the “right” or “correct” interpretations of particular phenomena or processes. When “incorrect” ideas of the past are mentioned at all, it is simply to point out their errors, with little attention as to why the ideas were put forward in the first place, or ever gained a following. A strong case can be made, however, for presenting contrasting or even what are considered today “wrong” hypotheses as a way of not only emphasizing the dynamic nature of science (which is punctuated throughout by controversies and contrasting views), but also as a way of helping students better understand the details and workings of contemporary views. This article will illustrate these claims by examining the work of embryologist-turned-geneticist Thomas Hunt Morgan in the early decades of the twentieth century.

Keywords

Chromosome Pair Darwinian Natural Selection Mendelian Ratio Chromosome Theory Mendelian Genetic 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Notes

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank Gary Borissy and the organizers of the 2010 T. H. Morgan Symposium at the Marine Biological Laboratory in Woods Hole, for the initial invitation to present this talk honoring the centenary of Morgan’s first paper on Drosophila. In preparing our separate talks for that occasion, I had many stimulating discussions with my good friend and colleague Jane Maienschein, who, as always, helped keep me on track. I also want to thank three anonymous reviews for Science and Education for their critical, but very helpful, comments.

References

  1. AAAS, American Association for the Advancement of Science. (1989). Project 2061, science for all Americans. Washington, DC: AAAS Publications.Google Scholar
  2. Allchin, D. (2001). To err and win a nobel prize: Paul Boyer, ATP synthase and the emergence of bioenergetics. Journal of the History of Biology, 35, 149.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Allen, G. (1966a). Thomas Hunt Morgan and the problem of sex determination. Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society, 110, 48–57.Google Scholar
  4. Allen, G. (1966b) General education in the sciences: The role of history and philosophy. CUEBS [Commission on Undergraduate Education in the Biological Sciences] News 3 (No. 3, December): pp. 1–5.Google Scholar
  5. Allen, G. (1968). Thomas Hunt Morgan and the problem of natural selection. Journal of the History of Biology, 1, 113–140.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Allen, G. (1970). Intellectual history as an organizing principle. The American Biology Teacher, 32, 277–280.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Allen, G. (1978). Thomas Hunt Morgan: The man and his science. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  8. Allen, G., & Baker, J. (2001). Biology: Scientific process and social issues. New York, NY: Wiley.Google Scholar
  9. Bateson, W. (1906). The progress is genetics since the rediscovery of Mendel’s paper. In J. Lotsy (Ed.), Progressus rei botanicae (pp. 368–418). Jena: Gustav Fischer.Google Scholar
  10. Boveri, T. (1902). Über mehrpolige Mitosen als Mittel zur Analyse des Zellkerns. Verhandlungen der Physikalische-medizinische Gesellschaft zu Würaburg 35:67–90. Translated and reprinted in part in Voeller, B. (1968), The chromosome theory of inheritance, New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts, pp. 85–94.Google Scholar
  11. Boveri, T. (1907). Zellen-studien VI, Die Entwicklung dispermere Seeigel Eier. Ein Beitrag aur Befruchtungsgelehre und zur Theorie des Kerns. Jenaische Zeitschrift für Naturwissenschaften, 43, 1–292.Google Scholar
  12. Bowler, P. (1996). Life’s splendid drama: Evolutionary biology and the reconstruction of life’s ancestry, 1860–1940. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  13. De Vries, H. (1901–1903). The Mutation Theory. Chicago, IL: Open Court Publishing Co., Two volumes.Google Scholar
  14. Falk, R. (2000). The gene—A concept in tension. In P. Beurton, R. Falk, H-J. Rheinbeerger (Eds.), The concept of the gene in development and evolution. Historial and epistemological perspectives pp. 317–348. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  15. Gooday, G., Lynch, J., Wilson, G., & Barsky, C. (2008). Does science education need the history of science? Isis, 99, 322–330.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Harman, O. (2004). The man who invented the chromosome: A life of Cyril Darlington. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  17. Harrison, R. G. (1937). Embryology and its relations. Science, 85, 369–374.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Kampourakis, K. (2013). Mendel and the path to genetics: Portraying science as a social process. Science & Education, 22, 293–324.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Kohler, R. E. (1994). Lords of the fly. Drosophila genetics and the experimental life. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  20. Maienschein, J. (1991). Transforming traditions in American biology, 1880–1915. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
  21. Maienschein, J., Laubichleer, M., & Loettgers, A. (2008). How Cn history of science matter to scientists? Isis, 99, 341–349.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Mix, M., Farber, P., & King, K. (1996). Biology: The network of life. New York, NY: Harper Collins.Google Scholar
  23. Monk, M., & Osborne, J. (1977). Placing history and philosophy of science on the curriculum: A model for the development of pedagogy. Science Education, 81, 405–424.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Moore, J. (1963). Heredity and development. New York, NY: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
  25. Morgam, T. H. (1935). The relation of genetics to physiology and medicine. Scientific Monthly, 41, 5–18.Google Scholar
  26. Morgan, T. H. (1903). Evolution and adaptation. New York, NY: Macmillan.Google Scholar
  27. Morgan, T. H. (1909). What are factors in Mendelian explanations? American Breeders Association Report, 5, 365–368.Google Scholar
  28. Morgan, T. H. (1910). Sex-limited inheritance in Drosophila. Science, 32, 120–122.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Morgan, T. H. (1911). Random segregation versus coupling in Mendelian inheritance. Science, 34, 384.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Morgan, T. H. (1913). Heredity and sex. New York, NY: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
  31. Morgan, T. H. (1916). A critique of the theory of evolution. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  32. Morgan, T. H. (1932). The scientific basis of evolution. New York, NY: W.W. Norton.Google Scholar
  33. Morgan, T. H., Sturtevant, A. H., Muller, H. J., & Bridges, C. B. (1915). The mechanism of Mendelian heredity. New York, NY: Henry Holt.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. NRC National Research Council (1996). National science education Standards. National Committee for Science Education Standards and Assessment. Washington, D.C.: National Academies Press.Google Scholar
  35. NRC National Research Council (2012). A framework for K-12 science education. Washington, D.C.: National Academies Press.Google Scholar
  36. Rudge, D. W., & Howe, E. M. (2009). An explicit and reflective approach to the use of history to promote understanding of the nature of science. Science & Education, 18(5), 561–580.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Sturtevant, A. H. (1965). A history of genetics. New York, NY: Harper and Row.Google Scholar
  38. Voeller, B. (Ed.). (1968). The chromosome theory of heredity. New York, NY: Appleton-Century-Crofts.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2013

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of BiologyWashington University in St. LouisSt. LouisUSA

Personalised recommendations