Journal of Risk and Uncertainty

, Volume 30, Issue 1, pp 21–62

Ranked Additive Utility Representations of Gambles: Old and New Axiomatizations

Article

Abstract

A number of classical as well as quite new utility representations for gains are explored with the aim of understanding the behavioral conditions that are necessary and sufficient for various subfamilies of successively stronger representations to hold. Among the utility representations are: ranked additive, weighted, rank-dependent (which includes cumulative prospect theory as a special case), gains decomposition, subjective expected, and independent increments*, where * denotes something new in this article. Among the key behavioral conditions are: idempotence, general event commutativity*, coalescing, gains decomposition, and component summing*. The structure of relations is sufficiently simple that certain key experiments are able to exclude entire classes of representations. For example, the class of rank-dependent utility models is very likely excluded because of empirical results about the failure of coalescing. Figures 1–3 summarize some of the primary results.

Keywords

coalescing component summing event commutativity gains decomposition ranked additive utility ranked weighted utility utility representations 

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Aczél, J. (1966). Lectures on Functional Equations and their Applications. New York: Academic Press.Google Scholar
  2. Aczél, J. (1987). A Short Course on Functional Equations Based on Applications to the Behavioral and Social Sciences Dordrecht-Boston-Lancaster-Tokyo: Reidel-Kluwer.Google Scholar
  3. Aczél, J. and M. Kuczma. (1991). “Generalizations of a ‘Folk-Theorem’ on Simple Functional Equations in a Single Variable,” Results in Mathematics 19, 5–21.Google Scholar
  4. Aczél, J., R.D. Luce, and A.A.J. Marley. (2003). “A Functional Equation Arising from Simultaneous Utility Representations,” Results Math. 43, 193–197.Google Scholar
  5. Anscombe, F.J. and R.J. Aumann. (1963). “A Definition of Subjective Probability,” Annals Math. Stat. 34, 199–205.Google Scholar
  6. Birnbaum, M.H. (1997). “Violations of Monotonicity in Judgment and Decision Making.” In A.A.J. Marley (ed.). Choice, Decision, and Measurement: Essays in Honor of R. Duncan Luce. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum, pp. 73–100.Google Scholar
  7. Birnbaum, M.H. (1999). “Paradoxes of Allais, Stochastic Dominance, and Decision Weights.” In J. Shanteau, B. A. Mellers, and D.A. Schum (eds.), Decision Science and Technology: Reflections on the Contributions of Ward Edwards. Norwell, MA: Kluwer Academic Publishers, pp. 27–52.Google Scholar
  8. Birnbaum, M.H. (2000). “Decision Making in the Lab and on the Web.” In M. H. Birnbaum (ed.). Psychological Experiments on the Internet. San Diego, CA: Academic Press, pp. 3–34.Google Scholar
  9. Birnbaum, M.H. (2004). “Tests of Rank-Dependent Utility and Cumulative Prospect Theory in Gambles Represented by Natural Frequencies: Effects of Format, Event Framing, and Branch Splitting,”Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 95, 40–65.Google Scholar
  10. Birnbaum, M.H. and D. Beeghley. (1997). “Violations of Branch Independence in Judgments of the Value of Gambles,” Psychological Science 8, 87–94.Google Scholar
  11. Birnbaum, M.H. and A. Chavez. (1997). “Tests of Theories of Decision Making: Violations of Branch Independence and Distribution Independence,” Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 71, 161–194.Google Scholar
  12. Birnbaum, M.H., G. Coffey, B.A. Mellers, and R. Weiss. (1992). “Utility Measurement: Configural-Weight Theory and the Judge’s Point of View,” Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance 18, 331–346.Google Scholar
  13. Birnbaum, M.H., and J. Navarrete. (1998). “Testing Descriptive Utility Theories: Violations of Stochastic Dominance and Cumulative Independence,” Journal of Risk and Uncertainty 17, 49–78.Google Scholar
  14. Casadesus-Masanell, R., P. Klibanoff, and E. Ozdenoren. (2000). “Maxmin Expected Utility over Savage Acts with a Set of Priors,” J. Econ. Theory 92, 35–65.Google Scholar
  15. Chew, S.H. (1983). “A Generalization of the Quasilinear Mean and Applications to the Measurement of Income Inequality and Decision Theory Resolving the Allais Paradox,” Econometrica 51, 1065–1092.Google Scholar
  16. Cho, Y.-H., R.D. Luce, and L. Truong. (2002). “Duplex Decomposition and General Segregation of Lotteries of a Gain and a Loss: An Empirical Evaluation,” Org. Beh. Hum. Dec. Making 89, 1176–1193.Google Scholar
  17. Choquet, G. (1953). “Theory of Capacities,” Annales Inst. Fourier 5, 131–295.Google Scholar
  18. Ellsberg, D. (1961). “Risk, Ambiguity, and the Savage Axioms,” Q. J. Econ. 75, 643–669.Google Scholar
  19. Fishburn, P.C. (1988). Nonlinear Preference and Utility Theory. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins Press.Google Scholar
  20. Ghirardato, P. and M. Marinacci. (2002). “Ambiguity Made Precise: A Comparative Foundation,” J. Econ. Theory 102, 251–289.Google Scholar
  21. Ghirardato, P., F. Maccheroni, M. Marinacci, and M. Siniscalchi. (2003). “A Subjective Spin on Roulette Wheels,” Econometrica 71, 1897–1908.Google Scholar
  22. Gilboa, I., and D. Schmeidler. (1989). “Maxmin Expected Utility with a Non-Unique Prior,” J. Math. Econ. 18, 141–153.Google Scholar
  23. Kahneman, D. and A. Tversky. (1979). “Prospect Theory: An Analysis of Decision Making Under Risk,” Econometrica 47, 263–291.Google Scholar
  24. Karmarkar, U.S. (1978). “Subjectively Weighted Utility: A Descriptive Extension of the Expected Utility Model,” Org. Beh. Human Performance 21, 61–72.Google Scholar
  25. Köbberling, V. and P.P. Wakker. (2003). “Preference Foundations for Nonexpected Utility: A Generalized and Simplified Technique,” Math. Op. Res. 28, 395–423.Google Scholar
  26. Krantz, D. H., R.D. Luce, P. Suppes, and A. Tversky. (1971). Foundations of Measurement, Vol. I. San Diego: Academic Press.Google Scholar
  27. Liu, L. (1995). A Theory of Coarse Utility and its Application to Portfolio Analysis. University of Kansas, Ph.D. dissertation.Google Scholar
  28. Luce, R.D. (1959). Individual Choice Behavior: A Theoretical Analysis. New York: Wiley.Google Scholar
  29. Luce, R.D. (1990). “Rational versus Plausible Accounting Equivalences in Preference Judgments,” Psychol. Sci. 1, 225–234.Google Scholar
  30. Luce, R.D. (1998). “Coalescing, Event Commutativity, and Theories of Utility,” J. Risk Uncert. 16, 87–114. Errata: 18, 1999, 99.Google Scholar
  31. Luce, R.D. (2000). Utility of Gains and Losses: Measurement-Theoretical and Experimental Approaches. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum, Errata: see Luce’s web page at http://www.socsci.uci.eduGoogle Scholar
  32. Luce, R.D. (2002). “A Psychophysical Theory of Intensity Proportions, Joint Presentations, and Matches,” Psych. Rev. 109, 520–532.Google Scholar
  33. Luce, R.D. (2003). “Increasing Increment Generalizations of Rank-Dependent Theories,” Theory Dec. 55, 87–146.Google Scholar
  34. Luce, R.D. (2004). “Symmetric and Asymmetric Matching of Joint Presentations,” Psych. Rev. 111, 446–454.Google Scholar
  35. Luce, R.D. and A.A.J. Marley. (2000). “Elements of Chance,” Theory Dec. 49, 97–126.Google Scholar
  36. Maksa, G. (1999). “Solution of Generalized Bisymmetry Type Equations Without Surjectivity Assumptions,” Aequationes Math. 57, 50–74.Google Scholar
  37. Marley, A.A.J. and R.D. Luce. (2001). “Ranked-Weighted Utility and Qualitative Convolution,” J. Risk Uncert. 23, 135–163.Google Scholar
  38. Marley, A.A.J. and R.D. Luce. (2004). “Independence Properties vis-à-vis Several Utility Representations,” submitted.Google Scholar
  39. Meginniss, J.R. (1976). “A New Class of Symmetric Utility Rules for Gambles, Subjective Marginal Probability Functions, and a Generalized Bayes’ Rule,” Proceedings American Statistical Association, Business and Economic Statistics Sec. 471–476.Google Scholar
  40. Ng, C.T. (2003). “Monotonic Solutions of Functional Equation Arising from Simultaneous Utility Representations,”Results in Mathematics 44, 340–361.Google Scholar
  41. Quiggin, J. (1982). “ A Theory of Anticipated Utility,” J. Econ. Beh. Org. 3, 323–343.Google Scholar
  42. Quiggin, J. (1993). Generalized Expected Utility Theory: The Rank-Dependent Model. Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers.Google Scholar
  43. Savage, L.J. (1954). The Foundations of Statistics. New York: Wiley.Google Scholar
  44. Schmeidler, D. (1989). “Subjective Probability and Expected Utility Without Additivity,” Econometrica 57, 571–587.Google Scholar
  45. Slovic, P., M. Finucane, E. Peters, and D.G. MacGregor. (2002). “The Affect Heuristic.” In T. Gilovich, D. Griffin, and D. Kahneman (eds.), Heuristics and Biases: The Psychology of Intuitive Judgment. New York: Cambridge University Press, pp. 397–420.Google Scholar
  46. Tversky, A. and D. Kahneman. (1992). “Advances in Prospect Theory: Cumulative Representation of Uncertainty,” J. Risk Uncert. 5, 297–323.Google Scholar
  47. von Neumann, J. and O.Morgenstern. (1947). Theory of Games and Economic Behavior, 2nd edition. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  48. Wakker, P. P. (1990). “Under Stochastic Dominance Choquet-Expected Utility and Anticipated Utility are Identical,” Theory and Decision 119–132.Google Scholar
  49. Wakker, P.P. (1991). “Additive Representations on Rank-Ordered Sets. I. The Algebraic Approach,” J. Math. Psych. 35, 501–531.Google Scholar
  50. Wang, T. (2003). “Conditional Preferences and Updating,” J. Econ. Theory 108, 286–321.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science + Business Media, Inc. 2005

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.University of CaliforniaIrvine
  2. 2.University of Victoria and University of GroningenGroningen

Personalised recommendations