Abstract
In this paper, I defend the existence of a moral duty to disobey the law and engage in civil disobedience on the basis of one of the grounds of political obligation—the Samaritan duty. Christopher H. Wellman has recently offered a ‘Samaritan account’ of state legitimacy and political obligation, according to which the state is justified in coercing each citizen in order to rescue all from the perilous circumstances of the state of nature; and each of us is bound to obey the law, as the state demands, because we each have a responsibility to help rescue others when this assistance is not unreasonably costly. Though Wellman recognizes that there can be reasons for disobeying the law and resisting injustice in otherwise legitimate states, he overlooks the possibility that at least some of these reasons could be Samaritan in nature, grounded in the duty to rescue people from peril. As I shall argue, the Samaritan duty supports obligations to disobey the law, when the law prohibits Samaritan rescues, and to engage in civil disobedience, when unjust laws and practices contribute to endangering people. The discussion proceeds as follows. After a brief overview of the Samaritan duty, I articulate my case for Samaritan duties to disobey the law, and duties to engage in civil disobedience when unjust laws, institutions, or practices enable what I call ‘persistent Samaritan perils’. I then examine and respond to several objections to my account: first, that the costs of law-breaking are unreasonable, and thus cannot be morally required; second, that individuals’ particular acts of protest and civil disobedience do not appear to make any difference to the rescue, and thus cannot be required; third, that I stretch the Samaritan duty beyond recognition; and fourth, that the Samaritan duty binds us to help people in need or peril anywhere, not particularly at home. I consider in conclusion the advantages and limits of my account of citizens’ Samaritan duties in the face of injustice.
Keywords
Samaritan duty Injustice Political obligation Civil disobedienceNotes
Acknowledgments
I have benefited from discussions with friends and audiences at Boston University, Clemson University, the Society for Applied Philosophy Annual Conference at St Anne’s College, Oxford, the International Social Philosophy Conference at Northeastern University, the Mentoring Project for Pre-Tenure Women Faculty in Philosophy at the University of Massachusetts, Amherst, the Rocky Mountains Ethics Congress at the University of Colorado, Boulder, and the Workshop on the Duty to Resist Oppression at the University of Connecticut, Storrs. Special thanks are owed to David Lyons, Ann Cudd, Jill Delston, Meena Krishnamurthy, Kristina Meshelski, Melissa Yates, Samuel Huang, Julia Nefsky, Erich Hatala Matthes, Kimberley Brownlee, Carol Hay, Daniel Star, and Gabriel O’Malley for their thoughtful comments on earlier drafts of the paper.
References
- Bailey, Alison. 1998. Privilege: Expanding on Marilyn Frye’s oppression. Journal of Social Philosophy 29: 104–119.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Bedau, Hugo. 1969. Civil disobedience: theory and practice. New York: Pegasus.Google Scholar
- Broome, John. 1999. Ethics out of economics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Brownlee, Kimberley. 2008. Penalizing public disobedience. Ethics 118: 711–716.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Brownlee, Kimberley. 2012. Conscience and conviction: The case for civil disobedience. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Chenoweth, Erica, and Maria J. Stephan. 2011. Why civil resistance works: The strategic logic of nonviolent conflict. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
- Cohen, Carl. 1971. Civil disobedience: Conscience, tactics, and the law. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
- Daniels, Norman. 2012. Reasonable disagreement about identified vs. statistical victims. Hastings Center Report 42: 35–45.Google Scholar
- Delmas, Candice. 2013. Political resistance: A matter of fairness. Law and Philosophy. doi: 10.1007/s10982-013-9189-y.Google Scholar
- Delmas, Candice. 2014. Samaritanism and political legitimacy. Analysis 74: 254–262.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Dworkin, Ronald. 2011. Justice for hedgehogs. Cambridge, Massachusetts: The Bellknap Press of Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
- Fabre, Cécile. 2002. Good Samaritanism: A matter of justice. Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 5: 128–144.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Fabre, Cécile. 2007. Mandatory rescue killings. Journal of Political Philosophy 15: 363–384.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Fabre, Cécile. 2009. Permissible rescue killings. In Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society CIX. 149–164..Google Scholar
- Feinberg, Joel. 1992. The moral and legal responsibility of the bad Samaritan. In Freedom and fulfillment, 175–196. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
- Feinberg, Joel. 1984. Harm to others. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
- Frye, Marilyn. 1983. The politics of reality: Essays in feminist theory. Freedom, California: The Crossing Press.Google Scholar
- Garrett, Aaron. 2010. Courage, political resistance, and self-deceit. Boston University Law Review 90: 1771–1783.Google Scholar
- Hare, Caspar. 2007. Voices from another world: Must we respect the interests of people who do not, and will never, exist? Ethics 117: 498–523.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Hare, Caspar. 2012. Obligations to merely statistical people. Journal of Philosophy 109: 378–390.Google Scholar
- Harvey, Jean. 2007. Moral solidarity and empathetic understanding. Journal of Social Philosophy 38: 22–37.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Hill Jr, Thomas E. 2010. Moral responsibility of bystanders. Journal of Social Philosophy 41: 28–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Hurka, Thomas. 2008. Proportionality and necessity. In War: Essays in political philosophy, ed. Larry May, 127–144. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
- Klarman, Michael. 2004. From Jim Crow to civil rights: The Supreme Court and the struggle for racial equality. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
- Klosko, George. 2005. Political obligations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Klosko, George. 2004-5. Duties to assist others and political obligations. Politics, Philosophy & Economics 3: 143–159.Google Scholar
- Klosko, George. 2003. Samaritanism and political obligation: A response to Christopher Wellman’s ‘Liberal theory of political obligation’. Ethics 113: 835–840.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Knowles, Dudley. 2012. Good Samaritans and good government. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 112: 161–178.Google Scholar
- Lefkowitz, David. 2007. On a moral right to civil disobedience. Ethics 117: 202–323.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Levenson, Laurie L. 1999. Criminal law: The necessity defense. National Law Journal October 11, B19.Google Scholar
- Lipkin, Robert J. 1983. Beyond good Samaritans and moral monsters: An individualistic justification of the general legal duty to rescue. UCLA Law Review 31: 252–290.Google Scholar
- Locke, John. 1980 [1690]. Second treatise of government. Ed. C. B. Macpherson. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Co.Google Scholar
- Lyons, David. 2013. Confronting injustice: Moral history and political theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Maimonides, M. 1954 [1180]. Mishneh torah—The book of torts. Ed. H. Klein. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
- Milligan, Tony. 2013. Civil disobedience: Protest, justification, and the law. London: Bloomsbury Academic.Google Scholar
- Murphy, Liam. 2000. Moral demands in nonideal theory. Oxford: University Press.Google Scholar
- Narveson, Jan. 1976. Intentional behavior and social science. Journal for the Theory of Social Behavior 6: 267–270.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Nefsky, Julia. 2013. How you can help, without making a difference. Unpublished manuscript.Google Scholar
- Oliner, Samuel P., and Pearl M. Oliner. 1988. The altruistic personality: Rescuers of Jews in Nazi Europe. New York: Macmillan.Google Scholar
- Rawls, John. 1999. A Theory of justice, rev ed. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
- Raz, Joseph. 1979. The authority of law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
- Renzo, Massimo. 2008. Duties of Samaritanism and political obligation. Legal Theory 14: 193–217.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Ripstein, Arthur. 2000. Three duties to rescue: Moral, civil, and criminal. Law and Philosophy 19: 751–779.Google Scholar
- Simmons, A.John. 2005. The duty to obey and our natural moral duties. In Is there a duty to obey the law?, ed. Christopher H. Wellman, and A. John Simmons, 91–196. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
- Singer, Peter. 1972. Famine, affluence, and morality. Philosophy & Public Affairs 1: 229–243.Google Scholar
- Small, Deborah, and George Loewenstein. 2003. Helping a victim or helping the victim: Altruism and identifiability. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty 26: 5–16.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Smith, William. 2013. Civil disobedience and deliberative democracy. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
- Spelman, Elizabeth V. 1988. Inessential woman: Problems of exclusion in feminist thought. Boston: Beacon Press.Google Scholar
- Suber, Peter. 1999. Civil disobedience. In Philosophy of law: An encyclopedia, ed. C.B. Gray II, 110–113. New York: Garland Pub. Co.Google Scholar
- Thomas, Laurence M. 1998. Moral deference. In Theorizing multiculturalism, ed. Cynthia Willett, 359–381. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
- Unger, Peter. 1996. Living high and letting die: Our illusion of innocence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Walker, A.D.M. 1988. Political obligation and the argument from gratitude. Philosophy & Public Affairs 17: 191–211.Google Scholar
- Walzer, Michael. 1967. The obligation to disobey. Ethics 77: 163–175.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Weinrib, Ernest J. 1980. The case for a duty of rescue. The Yale Law Journal 90: 247–293.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Wellman, Christopher H. 1996. Liberalism, Samaritanism, and political legitimacy. Philosophy & Public Affairs 25: 211–237.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Wellman, Christopher H. 2001. Toward a liberal theory of political obligation. Ethics 111: 735–759.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Wellman, Christopher H. 2005. Samaritanism and the duty to obey the law. In Is there a duty to obey the law?, ed. Christopher H. Wellman, and A. John Simmons, 3–89. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Woodward, Comer Vann. 2001 [1955]. The strange career of Jim Crow. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar