Res Publica

, 17:227 | Cite as

Rights Enforcement, Trade-offs, and Pluralism

Article

Abstract

This paper asks whether (human) rights enforcement is permissible given that it may entail infringing on the rights of innocent bystanders. I consider two strategies that adopt a rights-sensitive consequentialist framework and offer a positive answer to this question, namely Amartya Sen’s and Hillel Steiner’s. Against Sen, I argue that trade-offs between rights are problematic since they contradict the purpose of rights, which is to provide a pluralist solution to disagreement about values, i.e. to allow agents to act in accordance with their values. I further argue that Steiner’s compensation strategy does not succeed in avoiding trade-offs so it falls prey to the same criticism. I propose a non-trade-off solution that is implicit in the accounts discussed and is more consistent with the meta-ethical framework advocated by Sen. This solution relies on an enforceable duty to share in the costs of rights enforcement hence it entails a degree of redistribution for enforcement purposes.

Keywords

Conflicts of rights Trade-offs Enforcement Consequentialism Agent-relative reasons Pluralism 

References

  1. Caney, Simon. 1997. Diversity and the lexical priority of the right to equal freedom. Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 17: 147–163.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Dworkin, Ronald. 1984. Rights as trumps. In Theories of rights, ed. Jeremy Waldron, 153–167. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  3. Fabre, Cécile. 2007. Mandatory rescue killings. Journal of Political Philosophy 15: 338–363.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Hart, H.L.A. 1984. Are there any natural rights? In Theories of rights, ed. Jeremy Waldron, 77–91. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  5. Nagel, Thomas. 1979. The limits of objectivity. The Tanner lectures on human values. Available at http://www.tannerlectures.utah.edu/lectures/documents/nagel80.pdf. Accessed 1 April 2011.
  6. Nozick, Robert. 1974. Anarchy, state and utopia. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
  7. Pettit, Philip. 1987. Rights, constraints and trumps. Analysis 47: 8–14.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Sen, Amartya. 1982. Rights and agency. Philosophy & Public Affairs 11: 3–39.Google Scholar
  9. Sen, Amartya. 1990. Welfare, freedom and social choice: a reply. Recherches Economique de Louvain 56: 451–485.Google Scholar
  10. Steiner, Hillel. 1974. The natural right to equal freedom. Mind 83: 194–210.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Steiner, Hillel. 1990. Putting rights in their place. Recherches Economique de Louvain 56: 391–408.Google Scholar
  12. Steiner, Hillel. 1994. An essay on rights. Oxford, UK & Cambridge, USA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  13. Steiner, Hillel. 2008. Self-ownership and conscription. In The Egalitarian conscience: essays in honour of G.A. Cohen, ed. Christine Sypnowich, 88–102. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  14. Thomson, Judith Jarvis. 1992. The realm of rights. Cambridge, MA & London, England: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  15. Vallentyne, Peter, Hillel Steiner, and Michael Otsuka. 2005. Why left-libertarianism is not incoherent, indeterminate, or irrelevant: a reply to Fried. Philosophy & Public Affairs 33: 201–215.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Waldron, Jeremy. 1981. A right to do wrong. Ethics XCII: 21–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Waldron, Jeremy (ed.). 1984. Theories of rights. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2011

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.CRÉUM, Université de MontréalSucc. Centre-Ville MontréalCanada

Personalised recommendations