Advertisement

Res Publica

, Volume 16, Issue 3, pp 281–298 | Cite as

Framing, Reciprocity and the Grounds of Egalitarian Justice

  • Gabriel Wollner
Article

Abstract

John Rawls famously claims that ‘justice is the first virtue of social institutions’. On one of its readings, this remark seems to suggest that social institutions are essential for obligations of justice to arise. The spirit of this interpretation has recently sparked a new debate about the grounds of justice. What are the conditions that generate principles of distributive justice? I am interested in a specific version of this question. What conditions generate egalitarian principles of distributive justice and give rise to equality as a demand of justice? My paper focuses on relationalist answers to this question. Advocates of relationalism assume that ‘principles of distributive justice have a relational basis’, in the sense that ‘practice mediated relations in which individuals stand condition the content, scope and justification of those principles’. To say that principles of justice are ‘based’ on and ‘conditioned’ by practice mediated relations is ambiguous. I will here be concerned with advocates of what I call the relationalist requirement, viz. positions which assume that ‘practice mediated relations’ constitute a necessary existence condition for principles of egalitarian distributive justice. Relationalists who endorse this view come in different varieties. My focus is on relationalists that view social and political institutions as the relevant ‘practice mediated relation’. The question at stake, then, is this: Are institutionally mediated relations a necessary condition for equality to arise as a demand of justice? Strong relationalists of the institutionalist cast, call them advocates of the institutionalist requirement, differ in important respects. They argue about what set of institutions is foundationally significant, and they disagree on why only that institutional relation gives rise to egalitarian obligations of justice. My paper engages two ways of arguing for the institutionalist requirement: Julius’s framing argument and Andrea Sangiovanni’s reciprocity argument. The issue at stake are the grounds of egalitarian justice and I will argue that the institutionalist requirement is mistaken. It is not the case that egalitarian obligations of distributive justice arise only between and solely in virtue of individuals sharing a common institution.

Keywords

Grounds of justice Relationalism Institutions Basic structure Equality 

Notes

Acknowledgments

Earlier versions of this paper have been presented at graduate conferences and workshops in Darmstadt, Harvard, Manchester, Munich, Pavia and UCL. I would like to thank audiences there for very helpful comments, especially my commentators Lukas Stanczyk and David Holly. I am very grateful to my supervisor Michael Otsuka for discussing previous versions of the paper, to Andrea Sangiovanni for responding to my arguments and to Rob Jubb, Jeremy Farris and Jerry Cohen for extremely helpful written comments. Finally, I would like to thank the AHRC for funding the doctoral research from which this paper is taken.

References

  1. Abizadeh, Arash. 2007. Cooperation, pervasive impact, and coercion: On the scope (not site) of distributive justice. Philosophy and Public Affairs 35(4): 318–358.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Armstrong, Chris. 2009. Coercion, reciprocity and equality beyond the state. Journal of Social Philosophy 40: 297–316.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Blake, Michael. 2001. Distributive justice, state coercion, and autonomy. Philosophy & Public Affairs 30: 257–296.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Cohen, G.A. 1995. Self-ownership, freedom and equality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Cohen, G.A. 2000. If you are an egalitarian, how come you are so rich? Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  6. James, Aaron. 2005. Constructing justice for existing practice: Rawls and the status quo. Philosophy & Public Affairs 33: 281–316.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Julius, A.J. 2003. Basic structure and the value of equality. Philosophy & Public Affairs 31: 321–355.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Julius, A.J. 2006. Nagel’s atlas. Philosophy & Public Affairs 34: 176–192.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Murphy, Liam. 1999. Institutions and the demands of justice. Philosophy & Public Affairs 27: 251–291.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Nagel, Thomas. 1979. Equality, in mortal questions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  11. Nagel, Thomas. 2005. The problem of global justice. Philosophy & Public Affairs 33: 113–147.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Otsuka, Michael. 2006. Prerogatives to depart from equality. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 58.Google Scholar
  13. Pogge, Thomas. 1989. Realizing Rawls. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
  14. Pogge, Thomas. 2000. On the site of distributive justice: Reflections on Cohen and Murphy. Philosophy & Public Affairs 29: 137–169.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Pogge, Thomas. 2008. Wold poverty and human rights. Cambridge: Polity Press.Google Scholar
  16. Rawls, John. 1999. A theory of justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  17. Rawls, John. 2001. Justice as fairness: A restatement. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press.Google Scholar
  18. Risse, Mathias. 2008. The grounds of justice. Kennedy School Working Paper Series. Google Scholar
  19. Ronzoni, Miriam. 2009. The global order: A case of background injustice? A practice dependent account. Philosophy & Public Affairs 37: 229–256.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Sangiovanni, Andrea. 2007. Global justice, reciprocity, and the state. Philosophy & Public Affairs 35: 2–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2010

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.University College LondonLondonUK

Personalised recommendations