Free will, grace, and anti-Pelagianism

Article
  • 140 Downloads

Abstract

Critics of synergism often complain that the view entails Pelagianism (or at least semi-Pelagianism), and so, critics think, monergism looks like the only live (orthodox) option. Critics of monergism often claim that the view entails that the blame for human sin ultimately traces to God. Recently, several philosophers (including Richard Cross, Eleonore Stump, and Kevin Timpe) have attempted to chart a middle path by offering soteriological accounts which are monergistic (and thus avoid Pelagianism) but maintain the resistibility of God’s grace (with the aim of blocking the tracing of sin to God). In this paper, we present a challenge to such accounts of the resistibility of grace, namely that they imply that human beings are praiseworthy for omitting to resist God’s grace. Even if such views escape Pelagianism as it is typically defined, they fail to avoid the worry at the heart of prominent criticisms of Pelagianism concerning the praise for a human being’s salvation. At the end of the paper, we suggest three possible solutions to this problem.

Keywords

Free will Moral responsibility Omissions Pelagianism 

Notes

Acknowledgements

For very helpful comments on previous drafts of this paper, we thank Simon Kittle, Dan Miller, Michael Robinson, and the audience at the 2015 Far West Regional Meeting of the Evangelical Philosophical Society.

References

  1. Augustine. (1999). The gift of perseverance. In John E. Rotelle (Ed.), Answer to the Pelagians, IV. The Works of Saint Augustine, I/26 (Roland J. Teske, Trans.). Hyde Park, NY: New City Press.Google Scholar
  2. Bostyn, D., & Roets, A. (2016). The morality of action: the asymmetry between judgments of praise and blame in the action-omission effect. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 63, 19–25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Clarke, R. (2014). Omissions: Agency, metaphysics, and responsibility. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Cross, R. (2005). Anti-pelagianism and the resistibility of grace. Faith and Philosophy, 22(2), 199–210.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Dowe, P. (2000). Physical causation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Dowe, P. (2001). A counterfactual theory of prevention and ‘causation’ by omission. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 79(2), 216–226.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Eshleman, A. (2014). Moral responsibility. In Edward N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Summer 2014 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2014/entries/moral-responsibility/.
  8. Evans, J. (2010). Reflections on determinism and human freedom. In D. L. Allen, S. Lemke, & S. W. Lemke (Eds.), Whosoever will: A biblical-theological critique of five-point calvinism. Nashville, TN: B & H Publishing Group.Google Scholar
  9. Isaacs, T. (1997). Praiseworthiness and omitting to do what is wrong. The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 35(4), 473–493.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Keathley, K. (2010). Salvation and sovereignty: A molinist approach. Nashville, TN: B & H Publishing Group.Google Scholar
  11. Kittle, S. (2015). Grace and free will: Quiescence and control. Journal of Analytic Theology, 3, 89–108.Google Scholar
  12. Stump, E. (2001). Augustine on free will. In E. Stump & N. Kretzmann (Eds.), The Cambridge companion to Augustine. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Stump, E. (2003). Aquinas. New York, NY: Routledge.Google Scholar
  14. Timpe, K. (2007). Grace and controlling what we do not cause. Faith and Philosophy, 24(3), 284–299.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2017

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.University of CaliforniaRiversideUSA
  2. 2.Porterville CollegePortervilleUSA

Personalised recommendations