Skip to main content
Log in

The problem of evil and the suffering of creeping things

  • Article
  • Published:
International Journal for Philosophy of Religion Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Even philosophers of religion working on the problem of non-human animal suffering have ignored the suffering of creatures like insects. Sensible as this seems, it’s mistaken. I am not sure whether creatures like these can suffer, but it is plausible, on both commonsensical and scientific and philosophical grounds, that many of them can. If they do, their suffering makes the problem of evil much worse: their vast numbers mean the amount of evil in the world will almost certainly be increased by many, many orders of magnitude, the fact that disproportionately many of them live lives which are nasty, brutish, and short means that the proportion of good to evil in the world will be drastically worsened, and their relative lack of cognitive sophistication means that many theodicies, including many specifically designed to address animal suffering, would apply to their suffering only with much greater difficulty, if at all. Philosophers of religion should therefore more seriously investigate whether these beings can suffer and what, if anything, could justify God in allowing as much.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For ease, I will call people responding to the problem of evil “theodicists” even though someone responding to the problem of evil needn’t present a theodicy (they might, instead, take a skeptical line, explaining why we shouldn’t expect to have plausible explanations of God’s allowing evils). I will also call all stories about why God might allow evils “theodicies” even though some people think there is an important distinction between theodicies and what are called “defences” (with the former being attempts to give God’s actual reasons for allowing evil and the latter merely possible reasons, for some sense of “possible.”).

  2. Here’s an example. Dougherty (2014), in order to sidestep skepticism about animal consciousness, suggests that we focus not just on animal pain but also on animals’ objective lack of flourishing, which “doesn’t depend on one’s reflective or perceptive abilities” (79). This would seem to open the door to discussing the suffering of creeping things, since the most obvious reason for denying that creeping things can suffer at all would be skepticism about their ability to have certain relevant mental states (such as desires or pains). However, the account of objective flourishing Dougherty gives is, for no reason I see stated, only intended to apply to mammals, birds, and “possibly to some other non-mammal vertebrates” (78).

  3. For instance, Paul Draper told me this in conversation.

  4. Someone might deny this because they think there’s no such thing as bad, simpliciter (e.g., Kraut 2011). Alternately, one might agree that there is badness simpliciter but deny that the suffering of creeping things would be bad in that way, either because they deny that suffering is ever bad simpliciter or because they think something about creeping things makes their suffering unimportant. I don’t have space to properly engage with these views, so I will ignore them. In doing so, I am in line with assumptions present in most of the problem of evil literature, which routinely relies on judgments about value simpliciter and which routinely takes instances of any sort of suffering as paradigm examples of prima facie evils.

  5. See, e.g., Simon (2014).

  6. Claim (1) is taken to be true by Plantinga (2004), claim (2) is taken to be true-for-all-we-know by van Inwagen (2006, pp. 85–86), claim (3) is rejected in Murray (2008, chapter 3.3), but only after five pages have been devoted to it, and claim (4) is taken to be true by Dougherty (2014, chapter 8–9). (Murray 2008, chapter 4.3 also defends as true-for-all-we-know a kind of post-mortem soul-making theodicy for animals, though not one that involves their maturing into persons).

  7. This is one of several views discussed in Shelly Kagan’s unpublished paper “What is Ill-Being when Well-Being is Enjoying the Good?”

  8. I found several of the empirical sources cited in the next few paragraphs in Tomasik (2015a). That source, along with Tomasik (2015b), also includes many other sources which Tomasik thinks provide evidence for the ability of insects and similar creatures to suffer.

  9. Of course, the actual proportion is in dispute; a leading strategy for theodicists is to try to show that the prima facie proportion isn’t the real one.

  10. If they don’t, the proponent of the global argument could, of course, simply add something about the vast amount of non-horrendous arthropod suffering to the argument.

  11. Of course, skeptical theists, who think theism is just fine without an explanation of why allows evil, will not be much bothered by this point. I think skeptical theism fails, though I won’t try to argue for that here (but see Dougherty and McBrayer 2014 for the most complete examination of the cases for and against skeptical theism).

  12. For this example to do the relevant work, I need to assume that, in this case, which option I should prefer is a good guide to which option is better for me and that the badness of an option for me is, all else equal, a good guide to its badness simpliciter. Both of these seem pretty plausible to me in this context.

  13. The point was forcefully raised to me, in independent conversations, by Alex Jech, Laura Francis Callahan and Michael Rabenberg. Larry Temkin and Stuart Rachels will probably also be sympathetic to this point; see Temkin (2012) and Rachels (1998).

  14. Temkin (2012) calls it the anti-additive-aggregationist view, which is a little more perspicuous but also harder to say.

  15. I assume that an intuition, rather than an argument, undergirds the anti-aggregationist view. At any rate, both Temkin’s and Rachels’ sympathy for anti-aggregationism seems to be based on intuition and appeals to common sense, not on any argument.

  16. The argument is an example of what Temkin (2012) calls “spectrum arguments.” They trace back to Parfit (1984). The specific case here is essentially the same as one found in Temkin (2012, chapter 2), though Temkin draws a very different conclusion from it. (Temkin 2012 treats it as representing a paradox showing the inconsistency of several views we should want to hold, while Temkin 1996 treated a similar case as demonstrating that the “all-things-considered better than” relation is intransitive).

  17. The relation is transitive iff for all x, y, and z, if x is worse than y and y is worse than z, x is worse than z.

  18. See Huemer’s (2008, Sect. 3) criticism of Parfit’s “perfectionism” and Temkin’s (2012, chapter 2.2) criticism of James Griffin’s views on the discontinuity of value, both of which can be adapted so as to apply here.

  19. Even Temkin admits to seeing the “power and appeal” of the view that the relation is transitive and so is “loath to deny the view” (Temkin 2012, pp. 9–10).

  20. For some of these arguments, see Huemer 2008. For more sympathetic examinations of whether transitivity should be rejected, see Rachels (1998) and Temkin (1996, 2012) (and for a criticism of Temkin, see Voorhoeve 2013).

  21. A more thorough overview of r- and K-selection can be found in basically any encyclopedia or biology textbook. The relevance of reproductive strategy to flourishing and suffering is discussed in Ng (1995, pp. 269–272), and Tomasik (2015a).

  22. Adams (1999) and Stump (2010) endorse this principle regarding human suffering, while Dougherty (2014) and Pawl (2014) argue that it ought to be extended to any creature that can experience suffering.

  23. For a defence (having nothing to do with philosophy of religion) of the claim that some non-human animals (such as wolves) are not only capable of intentional action but are actual moral agents, see Bekoff and Pierce (2009).

  24. The former is mentioned several times; for the latter, see chapter 8.4.

  25. What Murray defends is actually the idea that there is value in the universe proceeding from chaos to order in an orderly way, not just in its being orderly.

  26. Or “is for all-we-know,” or whatever, depending on how much the objector to the argument from evil wants to prove.

References

  • Adams, M. M. C. (1999). Horrendous evils and the goodness of god. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barbauld, A. (1813). The history of insects. New York: printed and sold by Samuel Wood at the Juvenile Book Store, no. 357, Pearl Street.

  • Barron, A., & Klein, C. (2016). What insects can tell us about the origins of consciousness. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 113(18), 4900–4908.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Basset, Y., et al. (2012). Arthropod diversity in a tropical forest. Science, 338(6113), 1481–1484.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bekoff, M., & Pierce, J. (2009). Wild justice. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Broome, J. (2004). Weighing lives. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (2007). Invertebrate minds: A challenge for ethical theory. The Journal of Ethics, 11(3), 275–297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (1996). The conscious mind. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin, C. (1860). Correspondence with Asa Gray, dated May 22, 1860. http://www.darwinproject.ac.uk/entry-2814. Accessed 10 Oct 2014.

  • Davidson, D. (1975). Thought and talk. In S. Guttenplan (Ed.), Mind and language (pp. 7–23). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dougherty, T. (2014). The problem of animal pain: A theodicy for all creatures great and small. New York: Palgrave MacMillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dougherty, T., & McBrayer, J. (2014). Skeptical theism: New essays. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dussutour, A., et al. (2009). Individual and collective problem-solving in a foraging context in the leaf-cutting ant Atta colombica. Animal Cognition, 12(1), 21–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fox, D. (2007). Consciousness in a cockroach. Discover Magazine. http://discovermagazine.com/2007/jan/cockroach-consciousness-neuron-similarity. Accessed 30 Jan 2016.

  • Frost, R. (1969). Design. In E. C. Latham (Ed.), The poetry of Robert frost: The collected poems, complete and unabridged (p. 1969). New York: Henry Holt and Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hall, D. (2008). Popularity of insects. In J. L. Capinera (Ed.), Encyclopedia of entomology (2nd ed., pp. 2999–3006). New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hasker, W. (2008). The triumph of god over evil. Downer’s Grove, IL: Intervarsity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huemer, M. (2008). In defense of repugnance. Mind, 117(468), 899–933.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard, C. (2004). Fellow creatures: Kantian ethics and our duties to animals. The tanner lectures on human values, delivered at the University of Michigan. http://tannerlectures.utah.edu/_documents/a-to-z/k/korsgaard_2005.pdf. Accessed 30 Jan 2016.

  • Kraut, R. (2007). What is good and why? The ethics of well-being. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kraut, R. (2011). Against absolute goodness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laidlaw, J. (1995). Riches and renunciation: Religion, economy and society among the Jains. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mackie, J. L. (1955). Evil and omnipotence. Mind, 64(254), 200–212.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Murray, M. (2008). Nature red in tooth and claw: Theism and the problem of animal suffering. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ng, Y. K. (1995). Towards welfare biology: Evolutionary economics of animal consciousness and suffering. Philosophy and Biology, 10, 255–285.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ødegaard, F. (2000). How many species of arthropods? Erwin’s estimate revised. Biological Journal of the Linnean Society, 71(4), 583–597.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. (1984). Reasons and persons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pawl, F. (2014). The problem of evil and animal suffering: A case study. (Doctoral dissertation.) Saint Louis University: St. Louis, Missouri, 2014.

  • Plantinga, A. (2004). Supralapsarianism or ‘O Felix Culpa’. In P. van Inwagen (Ed.), Christian faith and the problem of evil (pp. 1–25). Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rachels, S. (1998). Counterexamples to the transitivity of better than. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 76, 71–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sabrosky, C. W. (1953). How many insects are there? Systematic Biology, 2(1), 31–36.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon, T. M. (1998). What we owe to each other. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwaerzel, M., et al. (2003). Dopamine and octopamine differentiate between aversive and appetitive olfactory memories in Drosophila. Journal of Neuroscience, 23(33), 10495–10502.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon, M. (2014). Fantastically wrong: Europe’s insane history of putting animals on trial and executing them. Wired. http://www.wired.com/2014/09/fantastically-wrong-europes-insane-history-putting-animals-trial-executing/. Accessed 2 Feb 2015.

  • Singer, P. (2016). Are insects conscious? Project Syndicate. https://www.project-syndicate.org/commentary/are-insects-conscious-by-peter-singer-2016-05#comments. Accessed 6 Mar 2016.

  • Sterba, J. P. (2012). From rationality to equality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stump, E. (2010). Wandering in darkness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Swinburne, R. (1998). Providence and the problem of evil. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Temkin, L. (1996). A Continuum Argument for Intransitivity. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 25, 175–210.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Temkin, L. (2012). Rethinking the good: Moral ideals and the nature of practical reasoning. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tomasik, B. (2015a). The importance of insect suffering. essays on reducing suffering. http://reducing-suffering.org/the-importance-of-insect-suffering/. Accessed 30 Jan 2015.

  • Tomasik, B. (2015b). Do bugs feel pain? Essays on reducing suffering. http://reducing-suffering.org/do-bugs-feel-pain/ Accessed 30 Jan 2015.

  • Tomasik, B. (2015c). The predominance of wild-animal suffering over happiness: An open problem. http://reducing-suffering.org/wp-content/uploads/2015/02/wild-animals_2015-02-28.pdf. Accessed 6 Mar 2016.

  • Tooley, M. (1991). The argument from evil. Philosophical Perspectives, 5, 89–134.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Valentine, J. W. (2004). On the origin of phyla. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Inwagen, P. (2006). The problem of evil. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Voorhoeve, A. (2013). Valuing intuition: Temkin’s critique of transitivity. Economics and Philosophy, 29(3), 409–423.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walters, E., et al. (2001). Defensive responses of larval Manduca sexta and their sensitization by noxious stimuli in the laboratory and field. Journal of Experimental Biology, 204, 457–469.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, C. B. (1964). Patterns in the balance of nature and related problems in quantitative ecology. New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yetter-Chappell, R. (2011). Welfarism vs. appreciating beauty. Philosophy Etc. http://www.philosophyetc.net/2011/12/welfarism-vs-appreciating-beauty.html. Accessed 1 Feb 2016.

  • Zabala, N. A., & Gomez, M. A. (1991). Morphine analgesia, tolerance and addiction in the cricket pteronemobius sp. (orthoptera, insecta). Pharmacology, Biochemistry and Behavior, 40(4), 887–891.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

For feedback on this paper, I am grateful to Rebecca Chan, Michael Rabenberg, and attendees at the 2015 Eastern Meeting of the Society of Christian Philosophers, especially Alex Jech, Laura Francis Callahan, and Paul Draper. I am also grateful to Oscar Horta, Brian Tomasik, and others who have drawn attention to the moral significance of wild animal suffering; it was thanks to work like theirs that I became aware of the possibility that the suffering of creeping things may be tremendously terrible in the aggregate.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Dustin Crummett.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Crummett, D. The problem of evil and the suffering of creeping things. Int J Philos Relig 82, 71–88 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11153-017-9619-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11153-017-9619-0

Keywords

Navigation