Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Hayek’s Constitution of Liberty—a guarded retrospective

  • Published:
The Review of Austrian Economics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Hayek’s Constitution of Liberty is justly regarded as making a comprehensive case for the protection of individual liberty against excessive government intrusion. But even as its ends are correct, its analysis of key conceptions of equality, coercion and monopoly is incomplete because of Hayek’s refusal to adopt a consistent theoretical framework that accounts for the difference between formal and substantive forms of regulation, on the one hand, and why the refusal to deal is critical in competitive markets but subject to regulation in monopolistic ones. His deep skepticism about central planning rests upon an overbroad account of collective ignorance that unwisely understates the dangers of self-interest in collective deliberations. That weakness then leads him to exhibit an excessive skepticism toward written constitutions on both matters of structure and individual rights, which in turn leads him toward undue deference to economic regulation of the economy.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Hayek, FA (2011 [1960]) The Constitution of Liberty: The Definitive Edition, reissued in 2011, in a definitive edition done with exceptional care by the late Ronald Hamowy (1937–2012), to whose memory this essay is dedicated. All page references are to this edition.

  2. For discussion, see Epstein, R (2006) How Progressives Rewrote the Constitution. Cato Institute, Washington. See also, infra, at Part Two for a brief discussion of the economic liberty point.

  3. See, for example, the discussion in Humphreys Executor v. United States (1935).

  4. For one particularly outspoken version of the point, see Hamburger, P (2014) Is Administrative Law Unlawful? University of Chicago Press, Chicago. For my somewhat more restrained views, see Epstein, R (2011a) Design for Liberty: Private Property, Public Administration, and the Rule of Law. Harvard University Press, Cambridge.

  5. See, for example, United States v. Lopez (1995), in which Justice Kennedy rejected a mechanical test “defining by semantic or formalistic categories those activities that were commerce and those that were not.” Yet that is precisely what is required to make any jurisdictional allocation work. For an extended discussion of linguistic relativism, as related to this case, see Epstein, R (2016) Linguistic Relativism and the Decline of the Rule of Law, Harv J Law & Pub Policy 39:583–630.

  6. The origin of the doctrine is in the concurring opinion of Justice Johnson in Gibbons v. Ogden (1824); for its modern explication, see Dean Milk v. Madison (1951).

  7. For an example of how this can be done in the law of nuisance, see Epstein, R (1979) Nuisance Law: Corrective Justice and it Utilitarian Constraints, J Legal Stud 8:49–102.

  8. See Justice Alito’s dissent in United States v. Alvarez, in which he notes why the difficulties of private enforcement justified public sanctions in stolen valor cases in which people publicly claimed medals and awards that they had not actually received. (2012)

  9. See Loving v. Virginia, which equivocates between the two rationales. (1967)

  10. U.S. Const. Art. I, § 8, cl. 1. For discussion, see Epstein, R (2014) The Classical Liberal Constitution: The Imperfect Question for Limited Government. Harvard University Press, Cambridge.

  11. This review considered Thomas Nixon Carver’s 1921 Principles of National Economy. Hale’s most vocal modern defender is Fried, B (1998) The Progressive Assault on Laissez Faire: Robert Hale and the First Law and Economics Movement. Harvard University Press, Cambridge. For my critique of both Hale and Fried, see Epstein, R (1998) The Assault That Failed: The Progressive Critique of Laissez Faire, Mich L Rev 97:1697–1721 (attacking Fried for insisting that Hale demonstrated that “liberty” and “property” were empty terms, even though he did not use the word “empty” in his article).

  12. For a clear awareness of the distinction, see A.L.A. Schechter Poultry Corp. v. United States (1935):

    The Act does not define “fair competition.” “Unfair competition,” as known to the common law, is a limited concept. Primarily, and strictly, it relates to the palming off of one’s goods as those of a rival trader. In recent years, its scope has been extended. It has been held to apply to misappropriation as well as misrepresentation, to the selling of another’s goods as one’s own—to misappropriation of what equitably belongs to a competitor. Unfairness in competition has been predicated of acts which lie outside the ordinary course of business and are tainted by fraud, or coercion, or conduct otherwise prohibited by law.

  13. For an overview of these critiques, see Simons, H (1944) Some Reflections on Syndicalism, J. Pol. Econ. 52: 1–25, Hutt, W (1930) The Theory of Collective Bargaining: A History, Analysis, and Criticism of the Principal Theories Which Have Sought to Explain the Effects of Trade Unions and Employers Associations Upon the Distribution on the Product of Industry. The Free Press, Glencoe IL.

  14. I critique this view in Epstein R (1999) Hayekian Socialism, 58 Md L Rev 271, 274–78.

  15. To see how this works in the constitutional framework, see Epstein R (1993) Bargaining with the State, Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ.

  16. For the entire Latin text, see Lawson FH (1950) Negligence in the Civil Law. Clarendon Press, Oxford.

    For my explication of how the method works, see Epstein R (1992) A Common Lawyer Looks at Constitutional Interpretation, Boston U L Rev 72:699–727.

  17. The Latin version comes from Hobbes, De Cive (of the citizen).

    […] ostendo primo conditionem hominum extra societatem civilem, quam conditionem appellare liceat statum naturæ, aliam non esse quam bellum omnium contra omnes; atque in eo bello jus esse omnibus in omnia.

    I demonstrate, in the first place, that the state of men without civil society (which state we may properly call the state of nature) is nothing else but a mere war of all against all; and in that war all men have equal right unto all things.

  18. For the formulation, see Gaius Institutes 1.1.

  19. See for the full Latin translation, etc. Digest 18.1.1 pr.

  20. The relevant Statute of Frauds is found at 29 Car. 2, c.3 (1677). Some variation of this statute is found in virtually every jurisdiction today, and is of especial relevance for transfers of real estate and guarantees, and in the creation of will substitutes.

  21. See, supra, at Part II.

  22. For the American cases, see Ploof v. Putnam (1908) that establishes the right to enter over the objection of the owner, and Vincent v. Lake Erie Transportation Co. (1910), which establishes the duty of compensation.

  23. For one discussion of the variations, see Colombatto E (2007) Hayek and Economic Policy. In: Marciano A, Josselin J (eds) Democracy, Freedom and Coercion: A Law and Economics Approach. Elgar, Cheltenham, UK.

  24. For some sense on how this works, see Brough W (1990) Liability Salvage—By Private Ordering, 19 J Legal Stud 95.

  25. The phrase “affected with the public interest” had been first articulated by Sir Matthew Hale (1670) in his treatise De Portibus Maribus, written in the late seventeenth century but published only later.

  26. For a nice summary of the relative advantages of the various systems, see Duquesne Light Co. v. Barasch (1989).

  27. For discussion, see Epstein R (2013) The History of Public Utility Regulation in the United States Supreme Court: Of Reasonable and Nondiscriminatory Rates, J Supreme Court History 38:345–368.

  28. See, for the exhaustive history, Bernstein D (2011) Reconstructing Lochner: Defending Individual Rights against Progressive Reform. University of Chicago Press, Chicago.

  29. This decision struck down a federal law under the Fifth Amendment.

  30. This decision invalidated a Kansas law under the Fourteenth Amendment.

  31. For the classic statement, see Ely J (1981) Democracy and Distrust: A Theory of Judicial Review. Harvard University Press, Cambridge.

  32. In dealing with many of these issues, Hayek is not alone. At one time, the dominant trope among judicial conservatives was a form of judicial restraint that follows in Hayek’s footsteps. Earlier in his career, Antonin Scalia was an explicit champion of that approach. See Epstein R (1985) The Active Virtues, Regulation 9:14.

  33. For the more extended critique, see Epstein R (1999) Hayekian Socialism, Md L Rev 58:271–299.

References

  • Bernstein, D. (2011). Reconstructing Lochner: Defending individual rights against progressive reform. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Boettke, P. (2014). Entrepreneurship, and the entrepreneurial market process: Israel M. Kirzner and the two levels of analysis in spontaneous order studies. Review of Austrian Economics, 27, 233–247.

  • Brough, W. (1990). Liability salvage—by private ordering. Journal of Legal Studies, 19, 95–112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, J. (1975). The limits of liberty: Between anarchy and leviathan. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burns, J. W. (1991). The new role of coercion in antitrust. Fordham Law Review, 60, 379–435.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carver, T. (1921). Principles of national economy (1921). Boston: Ginn and Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coase, R. (1959). The federal communications commission. Journal of Law and Economics, 3, 1–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Colombatto, E. (2007). Hayek and economic policy. In A. Marciano & J. Josselin (Eds.), Democracy, freedom and coercion: A law and economics approach. Cheltenham, UK: Edward Elgar Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ely, J. (1981). Democracy and distrust: A theory of judicial review. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, R. (1979). Nuisance law: corrective justice and it utilitarian constraints. Journal of Legal Studies, 8, 49–102.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, R. (1980). The static conception of common law. Journal of Legal Studies, 253–276.

  • Epstein, R. (1985). The active virtues. Regulation, 9, 14.

    Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, R. (1992). A common lawyer looks at constitutional interpretation. Boston University Law Review, 72, 699–727.

    Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, R. (1993). Bargaining with the state. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, R. (1998). The assault that failed: the progressive critique of Laissez Faire. Michigan Law Review, 97, 1697–1721.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, R. (1999). Hayekian socialism. Maryland Law Review, 58, 271–299.

    Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, R. (2006). How progressives rewrote the constitution. Washington: Cato Institute.

    Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, R. (2011a). Design for liberty: Private property, public administration, and the rule of law. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, R. (2011b). The natural law influences on the first generation of American constitutional order: Reflections on Philip Hamburger’s law and judicial duty. 6 J Law, Philo & Culture (pp. 103–130).

  • Epstein, R. (2013). The history of public utility regulation in the united states supreme court: of reasonable and nondiscriminatory rates. Journal of Supreme Court History, 38, 345–368.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, R. (2014). The classical liberal constitution: The imperfect question for limited government. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, R. (2016). Linguistic relativism and the decline of the rule of law. Harvard Journal of Law & Public Policy, 39, 583–630.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fried, B. (1998). The progressive assault on Laissez Faire: Robert Hale and the first law and economics movement. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M., & Friedman, R. (1980). Free to choose: A personal statement—the classic inquiry into the relationship between freedom and economics. New York: Harcourt.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuller, L. (1964). The morality of law. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ginsburg, D., & Menashi, S. (2016). Our illiberal administrative law. NYU J Law & Lib.

  • Hale, M. (1670). De Portibus Maribus.

  • Hale, R. (1923). Coercion and distribution in a supposedly non-coercive state. Political Science Quarterly, 38, 470–494.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hamburger, P. (2014). Is administrative law unlawful? Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hamilton, A. (1961). The federalist 1. In J. Cooke (Ed.), The federalist papers. Middletown: Wesleyan University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hare, R. (1997). Sorting out ethics. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, F. A. (1944). The road to serfdom. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, F. A. (1976). Law, legislation and liberty, volume 2: The mirage of social justice. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, F.A. (2011 [1960]). In R. Hamowy (Ed.) The constitution of liberty: The definitive edition. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

  • Hutt, W. (1930). The theory of collective bargaining: A history, analysis, and criticism of the principal theories which have sought to explain the effects of trade unions and employers associations upon the distribution on the product of industry. Glencoe IL: The Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Justinian, Digest

  • Kant, I. (1996). The metaphysics of morals. In M. Gregor (Ed., trans) Cambridge Texts, Cambridge.

  • Kant, I. (2002). Groundwork for the metaphysics of morals. In A. Zweig, T.E. Hill (Ed., trans) Oxford Philosophical Texts, Oxford.

  • Kirzner, I. (1987). Spontaneous order and the case for the free market society. In Ideas on liberty: Essays in honor of Paul Poirot. Foundation for Economic Education, Irvington-on-Hudson, NY.

  • Lawson, F. H. (1950). Negligence in the civil law. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Madison, J. (1961). The federalist 51. In J. Cooke (Ed.), The federalist papers. Middletown: Wesleyan University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1971). A theory of social justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rothbard, M. (2007). F. A. Hayek and the concept of coercion, Mises Institute. https://mises.org/library/fa-hayek-and-concept-coercion. Accessed 11 Aug 2016.

  • Simons, H. (1944). Some reflections on syndicalism. Journal of Political Economy, 52, 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weber, M. (1946 [1958]). Politics as a vocation. In H. Gerth & C. W. Mills (Eds.), From Max Weber: Essays in sociology. New York: Oxford University Press.

Cases

  • A.L.A. Schechter Poultry Corp. v. United States, 295 U.S. 495 (1935).

  • Adair v. United States, 208 U.S. 161 (1908).

  • Allnut v. Inglis, 104 Eng. Rep. 206 (K.B. 1810).

  • Bailey v. Drexel Furniture Co., 259 U.S. 20 (1922).

  • Chicago, Milwaukee & St. Paul Railway Company v. Minnesota, 134 U.S. 418 (1890).

  • Coppage v. Kansas, 236 U.S. 1 (1915).

  • Dartmouth College v. Woodward, 17 U.S. 518 (1819).

  • Dean Milk v. Madison, 340 U.S. 349 (1951).

  • Duquesne Light Co. v. Barasch, 488 U.S. 299 (1989).

  • In re Furman Street, 17 Wend. 649 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. 1836).

  • Gibbons v. Ogden, 22 U.S. 1 (1824).

  • Hammer v. Dagenhart, 247 U.S. 251 (1918).

  • Humphrey’s Executor v. United States, 295 U.S. 602 (1935).

  • Lochner v. New York, 198 U.S. 45, 75 (1905).

  • Louisville & Nashville Railroad Co. v. Barber Asphalt Pav. Co., 197 U.S. 430 (1905).

  • Loving v. Virginia, 388 U.S. 1 (1967).

  • Munn v. Illinois, 94 U.S. 113 (1876).

  • National Broadcasting Co., Inc. v United States 319 U.S. 190 (1943).

  • National Labor Relations Board v. Jones & Laughlin Steel, 301 U.S. 1 (1937).

  • Ploof v. Putnam, 71 A. 188 (Vt. 1908).

  • Post v. Jones, 60 U.S. 150 (1856).

  • Union Pac. R.R. Co. v. Pub. Serv. Comm’n of Mo., 248 U.S. 67, 70 (1918).

  • United States v. Alvarez, 132 S.Ct. 2537, 2557 (2012). (Alito, J. dissenting).

  • United States v. Darby, 312 U.S. 100 (1941).

  • United States v. Lopez, 513 U.S. 549 (1995).

  • Vincent v. Lake Erie Transportation Co., 124 N.W. 221 (Minn. 1910).

  • Wickard v. Filburn, 317 U.S. 111 (1942).

Statutes

  • A Standard State Zoning Enabling Act, 1926.

  • Civil Aeronautics Act of 1938, 49 U.S.C. § 401, et seq.

  • Clayton Antitrust Act of 1914, 15 U.S.C. § 12–27.

  • Communications Act of 1934, 47 U.S.C. § 151, et seq.

  • English Trade Disputes Act of 1906, 6 Edw. 7 c. 47

  • Fair Labor Standards Act of 1938, 29 U.S.C. § 201–219

  • Motor Vehicle Act of 1935, 49 Stat. 543.

  • National Labor Relations Act of 1935, 29 U.S.C. § 151, et seq. Norris-LaGuardia Act of 1932, 29 U.S.C. § 101, et seq.

  • Radio Act of 1927, 47 U.S.C § 4.

  • Sherman Act, 15 U.S.C. § 1–7.

  • Statute of Frauds, 29 Car. 2, c.3 (1677).

  • The Agriculture Adjustment Acts (1933–1938). Pub. L. No. 73–10, 48 Stat. 31; Pub. L. No. 75–430, 52 Stat. 31.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Richard Epstein.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Epstein, R. Hayek’s Constitution of Liberty—a guarded retrospective. Rev Austrian Econ 30, 415–446 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11138-016-0367-7

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11138-016-0367-7

Keywords

JEL classification

Navigation