Skip to main content
Log in

Walter Eucken’s place in the history of ideas

  • Published:
The Review of Austrian Economics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

German neoliberalism, as represented by the so called Freiburg School, was mainly influenced by the economist Walter Eucken. Eucken’s economic methodology can only be understood if placed in the context of the German philosophical and sociological debate of that time. The revelation of these connections is at the center of this paper. To this purpose, first, the influence of Max Weber and of his ideal typical approach will be discussed. Second, the role played by Walter Eucken’s father, the philosopher Rudolf Eucken and the significance of the Freiburg phenomenologist Edmund Husserl for the concept of ordoliberalism will be analyzed. Third, it will be shown that Eucken’s method is set against all relativist currents and sustained by the hope of discovering the “realm of truth” (Edmund Husserl) in economics as well. On this basis, Eucken’s oeuvre can be characterized by the aspects of order, freedom and truthfulness.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Weber’s “Habilitationsschrift” on Roman agrarian history already hints at this ideal type approach; cf. Weber (1891: 266).

  2. This is explained in his 1906 “Kritische Studien auf dem Gebiet der kulturwissenschaftlichen Logik” (Critical studies in the logic of the cultural sciences): “To be able to penetrate the real causal interrelations, we construct unreal ones” (Weber [1906] 1982: 287, my translation). For Weber, however, causal interrelations are not, of course, to be understood as objective principles: “Where the individuality of a phenomenon is concerned, the question of causality is not a question of laws but of concrete causal relationships; it is not a question of the subsumption of the event under some general rubric as a representative case but of its imputation as a consequence of some constellation. It is in brief a question of imputation.” (Weber [1904] 1949: 79). Indeed, one of Weber’s main criticism towards the epistemological principles of the Historical School was that it had failed to recognize this.

  3. One has to agree with Yuichi Shionoya (1996: 51) when he sums up: “Weber had one foot in German historical economics and the other foot in neo-Kantian philosophy.”

  4. Observe that Eucken begins his deliberations on the great antinomy with the following desideratum: “The first task of the economist is to get a grasp of economic reality” (Eucken [1940] 1950: 41).

  5. This trait elucidates why in Eucken’s epistemology, Menger’s approach is always presented along with the Rickert-Windelband theory of science (Eucken [1940] 1950: 55 f.).

  6. In this connection, Eucken gives credit to Menger especially for bringing to the fore the problems of his time: “Actually, it was Menger’s and his disciples’ main objective to do away with outdated tenets altogether and to take a fresh approach to things. This is why classical economics was criticized harshly, and often too harshly […] it was a new approach that the Austrians sought […] to not acknowledge this often declared and energetically pursued aim of theirs is tantamount to doing grave injustice to Menger’s and his disciples’ agenda” (Eucken 1940: 497, my translation, cross-referencing to Menger [1883] 1969: XV).

  7. “The question to what extent, for instance, today’s ‘abstract theory’ should be further elaborated is ultimately also a question of economy in scholarly inquiry (which is, after all, also faced with other problems). Thus, ‘marginal utility theory’ is itself subject to the ‘law of marginal utility’.” (Weber [1904] 1949: 89)

  8. “To solve corresponding concrete problems, about a century ago Thünen posed the agricultural location problem in general terms and constructed his thought experiment of the isolated state […] On the basis of this famous model, he succeeded in obtaining generalizable theoretical propositions. With theoretical tools like these, the analyst can turn to the real economy again to identify those connections which are of interest. The ‘real economy,’ along these lines, may be Mecklenburg agriculture of Thünen’s time, but just as well today’s East Prussian agriculture or, for that matter, the entire German agriculture” (Eucken (1938b: 18, my translation).

  9. With his appointment, Rudolf Eucken also prevailed over Friedrich Nietzsche, who was already teaching philology in Basel; cf. Graf (1997: 61 f.).

  10. The “Prolegomena” were re-printed in unaltered form in 1922, also featuring a review of his oeuvre, as “Prolegomena und Epilog. Zu einer Philosophie des Geisteslebens” (Prolegomena and Epilogue. On a Philosophy of Intellectual Life).

  11. In the Foundations as well, Eucken recurrently refers to Lotze’s “Logic” (Eucken ([1940] 1950: 40, 330, 332 and 350). Thanks to this specific work, Lotze is certainly to be considered one of the principal sources of inspiration for many thinkers of the late 19th and early 20th century. It is precisely because of this that it is difficult to argue (at least with regard to this specific publication) that there is a specific influence of Lotze on Eucken’s method.

  12. The Australian philosopher W. R. Boyce Gibson translated Rudolf Eucken and Edmund Husserl into English. This quote is taken from his diary, cited in Spiegelberg (1971: 69).

  13. Though Husserl’s objective is the “realm of transcendental order as an ‘absolute,’ in a specific sense, existence.”

  14. This notwithstanding, Eucken cites two further works by Husserl: we find a reference to the ‘Krisis’ essay published in 1936 (cf. Eucken 1938a: 199, note 1) and a reference to the ‘Logos’ essay of 1911 (cf. Eucken [1940] 1950: 321, note 4).

  15. Observe the direct analogy to Husserl’s introduction to the “Lehre von den Ganzen und Teilen” (On the Theory of the Wholes and the Parts): “The difference between ‘abstract’ and ‘concrete’ contents […] is most important for all phenomenological investigations” (Husserl [1900/1901] 1970: 435).

  16. A few lines later, he rejects the relativistic position of Spengler, Pareto and Mach: “The following is true also for Spengler, Pareto, Mach and the other relativists: however their respective relativist stances are formulated, they all assume absolute validity of their propositions. How can they be so sure? If they were consistent, they would have to declare their propositions to be conditional as well” (Eucken [1952] 2004: 343, my translation). Almost verbatim, this argument occurs as early as in Eucken (1938a: 199).

  17. A passage in a letter by Malvine Husserl dating from December 1930 shows that Edith Eucken-Erdsiek was familiar with phenomenological analysis: “Yesterday we spent a very nice and intellectually inspiring evening with Erik Wolf at the Euckens’ place, returning home only at 1 a.m. Father had a very good day, talking very arrestingly and not leaving his route for a second. Mrs. Eucken seconded cleverly and spiritedly” (cited in Husserl 1994, vol. IX: 390, my translation).

  18. Two weeks before the official appointment of Heidegger as President of the University of Freiburg, Walter Eucken complained that Heidegger “wanted to follow in the Führer’s footsteps. Apparently, Heidegger considers himself the born philosopher and the intellectual leader of the new movement, the only important and outstanding thinker since Heraclitus.” During Heidegger’s tenure, Eucken became the speaker for the latent opposition in the University of Freiburg Senate, as well as the foil of the Dean of the Faculty of Law and Economics, the jurist Erik Wolf, who, at that time, was an ardent admirer of Heidegger’s. Eucken ascribed to Wolf “fanaticism and ignorance of the legal situation” as well as an “idolatrous worship of Heidegger.” The tensions between the new leadership of the University and the Faculty on the one hand, and the professoral opposition led by Eucken on the other, escalated when Karl Diehl vacated the Chair for Economics and a successor had to be appointed. Heidegger, aggrieved in his vanity and in his claim to leadership, used these quarrels as a welcome excuse to resign from his position as President of the University. In a similar vein, Walter Eucken’s lecture “Der Kampf der Wissenschaft” (The battle of science) (summer term 1936) documents to what extent the belief in personal freedom characterizes Eucken’s role in the resistance against the Nazi regime. As Eucken writes in a letter to Alexander Rüstow in May 1936, the lecture’s aim was to give an “impression of the strength, dignity, dynamics of true science.” This, however, made Eucken’s lectures not only a meeting place for critics of the regime, but also an assembly point for ardent defendors of the new doctrine of the state—in order to polemicize there against Eucken and his views; cf. Goldschmidt (2002: chap. 4).

  19. Eucken’s value convictions cannot be reduced to a ‘Kantian freedom philosophy,’ a view often found in the literature (on the basics cf. Nawroth 1961). Instead, Eucken’s convictions are of the post-Kantian tradition. In order to confront the (nihilistic) danger of loss of values, Eucken explicitly endorses the ideas of a philosophy of values: “Only free will enables us to recognize and realize the mandatory ethical value order.” (Eucken [1952] 2004: 176, my translation). Hence, the notion of order is constitutive of the notion of freedom.

References

  • Blümle, G., & Goldschmidt, N. (2006a). From economic stability to social order: the debate about business cycle theory in the 1920’s and its relevance for the development of theories of social order by Lowe, Hayek and Eucken. European Journal of the History of Economic Thought, 13, 543–570.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blümle, G., & Goldschmidt, N. (2006b). ‘Gustav Schmoller, His heirs and the foundation of today’s social policy’, Schmollers Jahrbuch. Journal of Applied Social Science Studies, 126, 197–224.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caldwell, B. (2001). There really was a German historical school of economics: a comment on Heath Pearson. History of Political Economy, 33, 649–654.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eucken, R. (1925). Die Forderung einer gemeinsamen Gedankenwelt. Der Euckenbund, 1, 25–29.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eucken, R. ([1885] 1922) Prolegomena und Epilog, Berlin, Leipzig: Vereinigung wissenschaftlicher Verleger.

  • Eucken, W. (1926). Die geistige Krise und der Kapitalismus. Die Tatwelt, 2, 13–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eucken, W. (1932). Religion—Wirtschaft—Staat. Zur Problematik des Gegenwartsmenschen. Die Tatwelt, 8, 82–89.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eucken, W. (1938a). Die Überwindung des Historismus. Schmollers Jahrbuch, 62, 191–214.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eucken, W. (1938b). Nationalökonomie—wozu? Leipzig: Meiner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eucken, W. (1940). Wissenschaft im Stile Schmollers. Weltwirtschaftliches Archiv, 52, 468–506.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eucken, W. (1950) ‘Vorwort,’ in R. Eucken, Die Lebensanschauungen der Grossen Denker. Eine Entwicklungsgeschichte des Lebensproblems der Menschheit von Platon bis zur Gegenwart, 20th edn., Berlin: de Gruyter, V–VII.

  • Eucken, W. ([1934] 1954) Kapitaltheoretische Untersuchungen, 2nd ed., Tübingen: Mohr and Zürich: Polygraphischer Verlag.

  • Eucken, W. ([1940] 1950) The Foundations of Economics. History and Theory of Economic Reality, London: Hodge.

  • Eucken, W. ([1940] 1989) Die Grundlagen der Nationalökonomie, 9th edn., Berlin et al.: Springer.

  • Eucken, W. ([1952] 2004) Grundsätze der Wirtschaftspolitik, 7th edn., Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.

  • Eucken-Erdsiek, E. (1981). Magie der Extreme. Von der Schwierigkeit einer geistigen Orientierung. Herder: Freiburg.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fellmann, F. (1989). Phänomenologie als ästhetische Theorie. Freiburg: Alber.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, M. (2004) Geschichte der Gouvernementalität II. Die Geburt der Biopolitik, Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp.

  • Gadamer, H.-G. (1995). Hermeneutik im Rückblick. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gerber, D. J. (1994). Constituionalizing the economy: German neo-liberalism, competition law and the “New” Europe. The American Journal of Comparative Law, 42, 25–84.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldschmidt, N. (1998). Christlicher Glaube, Wirtschaftstheorie und Praxisbezug. Walter Eucken und die Anlage 4 der Denkschrift des Freiburger Bonhoeffer-Kreises. Historisch-Politische Mitteilungen, 5, 33–48.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldschmidt, N. (2002). Entstehung und Vermächtnis ordoliberalen Denkens. Walter Eucken und die Notwendigkeit einer kulturellen Ökonomik. Lit: Münster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldschmidt, N. (2005a). Die Rolle Walter Euckens im Widerstand: Freiheit, Ordnung und Wahrhaftigkeit als Handlungsmaximen. In N. Goldschmidt (Ed.), Wirtschaft, Politik und Freiheit. Freiburger Wirtschaftswissenschaftler und der Widerstand (pp. 289–314). Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldschmidt, N. (2005b). Hermann Schumacher—nur ein weiterer Erbe Schmollers oder der erste Ordoliberale? Anmerkungen zu einem “missing link” zwischen der Historischen und der Freiburger Schule. In J. Backhaus (Ed.), Historische Schulen (pp. 53–93). Münster: Lit.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldschmidt, N. (Ed.). (2005c). Wirtschaft, Politik und Freiheit. Freiburger Wirtschaftswissenschaftler und der Widerstand. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldschmidt, N. (2011) ‘Planning for freedom. The repression and opposition of economists during the Nazi regime in Germany on the example of the Freiburg Circles,’ in: Subsidiarity and Institutional Polyarchy. Studies of Social Market Economy in contemporary democracies, Centro Studi Tocqueville-Acton, Yearbook 2011, Soveria Mannelli: Rubbettino, 111–122.

  • Goldschmidt, N., & Berndt, A. (2005). Leonhard Miksch (1901–1950)—A forgotten member of the Freiburg School. American Journal of Economics and Sociology, 64, 973–998.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldschmidt, N. and H. Rauchenschwandtner (2007) The Philosophy of Social Market Economy: Michel Foucault’s Analysis of Ordoliberalism, Freiburg Discussion Papers on Constitutional Economics 07/4.

  • Goldschmidt, N., & Wohlgemuth, M. (2008). Social Market Economy: origins, meanings and interpretations. Constitutional Political Economy, 19, 261–276.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Graf, F. W. (1997). Die Positivität des Geistigen. Rudolf Euckens Programm neoidealisitscher Universalintegration. In G. Hübinger, R. vom Bruch, & F. W. Graf (Eds.), Kultur und Kulturwissenschaften um 1900. II. Idealismus und Positivismus (pp. 53–85). Stuttgart: Steiner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hekman, S. J. (1983). Weber, the ideal type, and contemporary social theory. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodgson, G. M. (2001). How economics forgot history. the problem of historical specifity in social science. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1994). Briefwechsel. Vol. I-IX. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. ([1900/1901] 1970) Logical Investigations. Translated by J.N. Findlay, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

  • Husserl, E. ([1910/11] 1965) ‘Philosophy as a Rigorous Science,’ in: E. Husserl, Phenomenology and the Crisis of Philosophy. Translated with an introduction by Quentin Lauer, New York: Harper & Row, 71–147.

  • Husserl, E. ([1913] 1958) Ideas. General Introduction to Pure Phenomenology. Translated by W.R. Boyce Gibson, London: Allen & Unwin, New York: Macmillan.

  • Husserl, E. ([1929] 1960) Cartesian Meditations. An Introduction to Phenomenology. Translated by Dorion Cairns, The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

  • Husserl, E. ([1936] 1970) The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology. An Introduction to Phenomenological Philosophy, Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

  • Janssen, H. (2000). Nationalökonomie und Nationalsozialismus. Die deutsche Volkswirtschaftslehre in den dreißiger Jahren (2nd ed.). Marburg: Metropolis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klump, R., & Wörsdörfer, M. (2011). On the affiliation of phenomenology and ordoliberalism: links between Edmund Husserl, Rudolf and Walter Eucken. European Journal of the History of Economic Thought, 18, 551–578.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lenel, H. O. (1991). Walter Euckens Briefe an Alexander Rüstow. ORDO, 42, 11–14.

    Google Scholar 

  • Megay, E. N. (1970). Anti-pluralist liberalism: the German neoliberals. Political Science Quarterly, 85, 422–442.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Menger, C. ([1883] 1969) Untersuchungen über die Methode der Sozialwissenschaften, und der Politischen Oekonomik insbesondere, Leipzig: Duncker & Humblot.

  • Nawroth, E. E. (1961). Die Sozial- und Wirtschaftsphilosophie des Neoliberalismus. Heidelberg, Löwen: Kerle u. Nauwelaerts.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oliver, H. M. (1960). German neoliberalism. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 74, 117–149.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pearson, H. (1999). Was there really a German historical school of economics? History of Political Economy, 31, 547–562.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rickert, H. (1902). Die Grenzen der naturwissenschaftlichen Begriffsbildung. Eine logische Einleitung in die historischen Wissenschaften. Tübingen: Mohr.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rieter, H., & Schmolz, M. (1993). The Ideas of German Ordoliberalism 1938–45: pointing the way to a new economic order. European Journal of the History of Economic Thought, 1, 87–114.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sally, R. (1998). Classical Liberalism and International Economic Order: Studies in theory and intellectual history. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schefold, B. (1996). The German historical school and the belief in ethical progress. In F. N. Brady (Ed.), Ethical iniversals in international business (pp. 173–196). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Scheler, M. (1973). Wesen und Formen der Sympathie/Die deutsche Philosophie der Gegenwart. Bern: Francke.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shionoya, Y. (1996). Getting Back Max Weber from sociology to economics. In H. Rieter (Ed.), Studien zur Entwicklung der ökonomischen Theorie XI: Die Darstellung der Wirtschaft und der Wirtschaftswissenschaften in der Belletristik (pp. 47–66). Berlin: Duncker & Humblot.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sombart, W., M. Weber and E. Jaffé (1904) ‘Geleitwort,’ Archiv für Sozialwissenschaft und Sozialpolitik 19: I–VIII.

  • Spiegelberg, H. (1971). From Husserl to Heidegger. Excerpts from a 1928 Freiburg Diary by W.R. Boyce Gibson. Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology, 2, 58–81.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vanberg, V. J. (1988). “Ordnungstheorie” as constitutional economics. The German conception of a ‘social market economy. ORDO, 39, 17–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vanberg, V. J. (2005). Market and state: the perspective of constitutional political economy. Journal of Institutional Economics, 1, 23–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weber, M. (1891). Die römische Agrargeschichte in ihrer Bedeutung für das Staats- und Privatrecht. Stuttgart: Enke.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, M. (1924). Gesammelte Aufsätze zur Sozial- und Wirtschaftsgeschichte. Tübingen: Mohr.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, M. ([1904] 1949) ‘“Objectivity” in Social Science and Social Policy, in Max Weber on the Methodology of the Social Sciences, ed. by E.A. Shils and H.A. Finch, New York: Free Press of Glencoe, 49–112.

  • Weber, M. ([1906] 1982) Kritische Studien auf dem Gebiet der kulturwissenschaftlichen Logik, in M. Weber, Gesammelte Aufsätze zur Wissenschaftstheorie, 5th ed., Tübingen: Mohr, 215–290.

  • Weber, M. ([1908] 1982) Die Grenznutzenlehre und das “psychologische Grundgesetz”, in M. Weber, Gesammelte Aufsätze zur Wissenschaftstheorie, 5th ed., Tübingen: Mohr, 384–399.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Nils Goldschmidt.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Goldschmidt, N. Walter Eucken’s place in the history of ideas. Rev Austrian Econ 26, 127–147 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11138-013-0222-z

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11138-013-0222-z

Keywords

JEL classification

Navigation