Advertisement

Epistemic akrasia and higher-order beliefs

  • Timothy KearlEmail author
Article

Abstract

According to the Fragmentation Analysis, epistemic akrasia is a state of conflict between beliefs formed by the linguistic and non-linguistic belief-formation systems, and epistemic akrasia is irrational because it is a state of conflict between beliefs so formed. I argue that there are cases of higher-order epistemic akrasia, where both beliefs are formed by the linguistic belief-formation system. Because the Fragmentation Analysis cannot accommodate this possibility, the Fragmentation Analysis is incorrect. I consider three objections to the possibility of higher-order epistemic akrasia. Along the way, I offer a revision of the Fragmentation Analysis that can allow for the possibility of higher-order akrasia while avoiding the problems I point out for the original view.

Keywords

Epistemology Epistemic akrasia Fragmentation Rationality 

Notes

References

  1. Aumann, R. (1992). Irrationality in game theory. In P. Dasgupta, et al. (Eds.), Economic analysis of markets and games, essays in honor of Frank Hahn (pp. 214–227). Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  2. Berry, D., & Dienes, Z. (1993). Implicit learning: Theoretical and empirical issues. Mahwah: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.Google Scholar
  3. Christensen, D. (2013). Epistemic modesty defended. In D. Christensen & J. Lackey (Eds.), The epistemology of disagreement: New essays. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Cushman, F. (2013). Action, outcome, and value: A dual-system framework for morality. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 17(3), 273–292.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Devine, P. (1989). Stereotypes and prejudice: Their automatic and controlled components. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 56, 5–18.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Egan, A. (2008). Seeing and believing: Perception, belief formation and the divided mind. Philosophical Studies, 140(1), 37–47.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Elga, A. & Rayo, A. Fragmentation and information access. https://www.dropbox.com/sh/8as1ofsyw5sxgfn/AADkIivF1WUYjvElmr3ZZLNa/fragmentation-and-information-access-2015-04-08.pdf?dl=0 (unpublished manuscript).
  8. Evans, J. (2007). Dual-processing accounts of reasoning, judgment, and social cognition. Annual Review of Psychology, 59, 255–278.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Evans, J. (2010). Thinking twice: Two minds in one brain. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  10. Evans, J., & Stanovich, K. (2013). Dual-process theories of higher cognition: Advancing the debate. Perspectives on Psychological Science., 8(3), 223–241.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Gendler, T. (2008). Alief and belief. Journal of Philosophy, 105(10), 634–663.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Gibbard, A. (1990). Wise choices, apt feelings: A theory of normative judgment. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  13. Gibbard, A. (2008). Thinking how to live. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  14. Greco, D. (2014). A puzzle about epistemic akrasia. Philosophical Studies, 167, 201–219.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Greco, D. (2015). Iteration and fragmentation. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 88(1), 656–673.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Horowitz, S. (2014). Epistemic akrasia. Nous, 48(4), 718–744.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Lewis, D. (1982). Logic for equivocators. Nous, 16(3), 431–441.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Paivio, A. (2007). Mind and its evolution: A dual coding theoretical approach. Mahwah: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates Publishers.Google Scholar
  19. Priest, G. (2000). The logic of backwards inductions. Economics and Philosophy, 16(2), 267–285.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Schwitzgebel, E. (2012). Introspection, what? In D. Smithies & D. Stoljar (Eds.), Introspection and consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  21. Sosa, E. (2007). A virtue epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Stalnaker, R. (1984). Inquiry. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  23. Stanovich, K., & West, R. (2000). Individual differences in reasoning: Implications for the rationality debate? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 23, 645–726.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Stanovich, K., & West, R. (2011). The complexity of developmental predictions from dual process models. Developmental Review, 31, 103–108.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  26. Williamson, T. (2011). Improbable knowing. In T. Dougherty (Ed.), Evidentialism and its discontents. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature B.V. 2019

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.University of ArizonaTucsonUSA

Personalised recommendations