Advertisement

Science, substance and spatial appearances

  • Thomas RaleighEmail author
Article

Abstract

According to a certain kind of naïve or folk understanding of physical matter, everyday ‘solid’ objects are composed of a homogeneous, gap-less substance, with sharply defined boundaries, which wholly fills the space they occupy. A further claim is that our perceptual experience of the environment represents or indicates that the objects around us conform to this sort of conception of physical matter. Were this further claim correct, it would mean that the way that the world appears to us in experience conflicts with the deliverances of our best current scientific theories in the following respect: perceptual experience would be intrinsically misleading concerning the structure of physical matter. I argue against this further claim. Experience in itself is not committed to, nor does it provide evidence for, any such conception of the nature of physical matter. The naïve/folk conception of matter in question cannot simply be ‘read-off’ from perceptual appearances.

Keywords

Visual experience Spatial experience Representational content Visual appearances Optical illusions Eddington Perception Philosophy of mind 

Notes

References

  1. Anscombe, G. E. M. (1963/1959) An Introduction to Wittgenstein’s Tractatus (2nd Revised ed.). New York: Harper & Row.Google Scholar
  2. Bayne, T. (2009). Perception and the reach of phenomenal content. Philosophical Quarterly, 59(236), 385–404.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Baysan, U., & Wilson, J. (2017). Must strong emergence collapse? Philosophica, 91, 49–104.Google Scholar
  4. Brogaard, B. (2013). Do we perceive natural kind properties? Philosophical Studies, 162(1), 35–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Cambell, J., & Cassam, Q. (2014). Berkeley’s Puzzle: What does experience teach us? Oxford: OUP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Carrasco, M. (2011). Visual attention: The past 25 years. Vision Research, 51, 1484–1525.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Casullo, A. (1986). The spatial structure of perceptual space. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 46(4), 665–671.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Chalmers, D. (forthcoming). Three puzzles about spatial experience. In A. Pautz and D. Stoljar (eds.), Themes from Ned Block. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  9. Clark, A. (2000). A Theory of Sentience. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Cussins, A. (1990). Content, conceptual content, and nonconceptual content. In Y. Gunther (Ed.), Essays on Nonconceptual Content (pp. 133–163). Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  11. Cutter, B. (forthcoming) Indeterminate perception and color relationism. Analysis.Google Scholar
  12. Dretske, F. (1995). Naturalizing the Mind. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  13. Eddington, A. (1928). The Nature of the Physical World. London: Dent.Google Scholar
  14. Eddington, A. (1939). Philosophy of Physical Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  15. Esfeld, M. (2009). The modal nature of structures in ontic structural realism. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 23, 179–194.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. French, S., & Ladyman, J. (2003). Remodelling structural realism: Quantum physics and the metaphysics of structure. Synthese, 136, 31–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Ganson, T., & Bronner, B. (2013). Visual prominence and representationalism. Philosophical Studies, 164(2), 405–418.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Gillet, C. (2002). Strong emergence as a defense of non-reductive physicalism. Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology, 6(1), 87–120.Google Scholar
  19. Gillet, C. (2003). The metaphysics of realization, multiple realizability, and the special sciences. The Journal of Philosophy, 100, 591–603.Google Scholar
  20. Gobell, J., & Carrasco, M. (2005). Attention alters the appearance of spatial frequency and gap size. Psychological Science, 16(8), 644–651.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Masrour, F. (2015). The geometry of visual space and the nature of visual experience. Philosophical Studies, 172(7), 1813–1832.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Maxwell, G. (1970). Structural realism and the meaning of theoretical terms. In S. Winokur & M. Radner (Eds.), Analyses of theories, and methods of physics and psychology. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
  23. Meadows, P. (2011). Contemporary arguments for a geometry of visual experience. European Journal of Philosophy, 19(3), 408–430.Google Scholar
  24. Nanay, B. (2010). Attention and perceptual content. Analysis, 70, 263–270.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Nanay, B. (2011). Do we see apples as edible? Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 92(3), 305–322.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Nanay, B. (2018). Blur and perceptual content. Analysis, 78(2), 254–260.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Peacocke, (1992). Scenarios, concepts, and perception. In Tim Crane (Ed.), The Contents of Experience. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  28. Pereboom, D. (2002). Robust non-reductive materialism. Journal of Philosophy, 99, 499–531.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Price, R. (2009). Aspect-switching and visual phenomenal character. Philosophical Quarterly, 59(236), 508–518.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Raleigh, T. (2009). Understanding how experience ‘seems’. European Journal of Analytic Philosophy, 5(2), 67–78.Google Scholar
  31. Russell, B. (1927). The Analysis of Matter. London: George Allen & Unwin.Google Scholar
  32. Sellars, W. (1962). Philosophy and the scientific image of man. In Robert Colodny (Ed.), Frontiers of Science and Philosophy. Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh Press.Google Scholar
  33. Siegel, S. (2006). Which properties are represented in perception? In J. Hawthorne & T. Gendler Szabo (Eds.), Perceptual Experience (pp. 481–503). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Stazicker, J. (2011). Attention, visual consciousness and indeterminacy. Mind & Language, 26(2), 156–184.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Tye, M. (1995). Ten Problems of Consciousness. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  36. Van Cleve, J. (2002). Thomas Reid’s geometry of visibles. The Philosophical Review, 111, 373–416.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Wagner, M. (2006). The Geometries of Visual Space. London: Erlbaum.Google Scholar
  38. Wilson, J. (2010). Non-reductive physicalism and degrees of freedom. British Journal for Philosophy of Science, 61(2), 279–311.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Wilson, J. (2011). Non-reductive realization and the powers-based subset strategy. The Monist, 94, 121–154.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Wilson, J. (2015). Metaphysical Emergence: Weak and Strong. In T. Bigaj & C. Wuthrich (Eds.), Metaphysics in Contemporary Physics: Poznan studies in the philosophy of the sciences and the humanities (pp. 345–402). Leiden: Brill.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Worrall, J. (1989). Structural realism: The best of both worlds? In D. Papineau (Ed.), The Philosophy of Science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  42. Yeshurun, Y., & Carrasco, M. (2008). The effects of transient attention on spatial resolution and the size of the attentional cue. Perception and Psychophysics, 70(1), 104–113.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature B.V. 2019

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyUnited Arab Emirates UniversityAl AinUnited Arab Emirates

Personalised recommendations