Advertisement

Interpretivism and norms

  • Devin Sanchez CurryEmail author
Article
  • 519 Downloads

Abstract

This article reconsiders the relationship between interpretivism about belief and normative standards. Interpretivists have traditionally taken beliefs (and thus veridicality conditions for belief attribution) to be fixed in relation to norms of interpretation. However, recent work by philosophers and psychologists reveals that human belief attribution practices are governed by a rich diversity of normative standards. Interpretivists thus face a dilemma: either give up on the idea that belief is constitutively normative or countenance a context-sensitive disjunction of norms that constitute belief. Either way, interpretivists should embrace the intersubjective indeterminacy of belief.

Keywords

Belief Normativity Intersubjective indeterminacy Relativism Davidson Dennett 

Notes

Acknowledgements

I have received invaluable feedback on the ideas presented in this article from Kristin Andrews, Ben Baker, Marie Barnett, Liz Camp, Amelia Curry, David Curry, Louise Daoust, Zoltan Domotor, Nabeel Hamid, Gary Hatfield, Brian Huss, Raffi Krut-Landau, Errol Lord, Lisa Miracchi, Bob Myers, Bjørn Ramberg, Quayshawn Spencer, Jordan Taylor, Claudine Verheggen, Michael Weisberg, Rob Willison, Ben Winokur, and two anonymous referees for this journal. The opening parable was inspired by a conversation with the Rev. Dr. Geoffrey Lentz, Pastor of the First United Methodist Church of Port St. Joe, Florida. Thanks also to participants in the 2017 conference on The Legacy of Donald Davidson at York University, as well as audiences at SUNY Potsdam, Kenyon College, and The College of Wooster. Any remaining flaws in my argument should be blamed on the bomb cyclone that prevented philosophers from attending my talk at the 2018 Eastern APA on an island in Savannah, Georgia. This research was partially supported by a Mellon/ACLS Dissertation Completion Fellowship from the American Council of Learned Societies.

References

  1. Ames, D. R. (2004). Inside the mind reader’s tool kit: projection and stereotyping in mental state inference. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 87(3), 340–353.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Andrews, K. (2015). The folk psychological spiral: explanation, regulation, and language. Southern Journal of Philosophy, 53(S1), 50–67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Antony, L. (2013). “Human nature” and its role in feminist theory. In S. Downes & E. Machery (Eds.), Arguing about human nature (pp. 521–542). Abingdon: Routledge.Google Scholar
  4. Appiah, K. A. (1985). The uncompleted argument: Du Bois and the illusion of race. Critical Inquiry, 12(1), 21–37.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Baker, L. R. (1995). Explaining attitudes. Cambridge: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Boghossian, P. (2007). Fear of knowledge: Against relativism and constructivism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  7. Bohl, V. (2015). We read minds to shape relationships. Philosophical Psychology, 28(5), 674–694.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Boudry, M., & Coyne, J. (2016). Disbelief in belief: On the cognitive status of supernatural beliefs. Philosophical Psychology, 29, 601–615.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Buttelmann, D., Daum, M., Zmyj, N., & Carpenter, M. (2013). Selective imitation of in-group over out-group members in 14-month-old infants. Child Development, 84(2), 422–428.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Carruthers, P. (2011). The opacity of mind: An integrative theory of self-knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Catechism of the Catholic Church. (1994). http://www.vatican.va/archive/eng0015/_index.htm.
  12. Cummins, R. (1996). Representations, targets, and attitudes. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  13. Curry, D. S. (2018a). Beliefs as inner causes: the (lack of) evidence. Philosophical Psychology, 31(6), 850–877.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Curry, D. S. (2018b). How beliefs are like colors. Publicly Accessible Penn Dissertations. 2991. https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations/2991.
  15. Davidson, D. (2001a). Essays on actions and events. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Davidson, D. (2001b). Inquiries into truth and interpretation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Davidson, D. (2001c). Subjective, intersubjective, objective. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Dennett, D. (1987). The intentional stance. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  19. Dennett, D. (1998). Brainchildren. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  20. Du Bois, W. E. B. (1897). The conservation of races. Washington, D.C.: American Negro Academy.Google Scholar
  21. Engel, P. (2008). Davidson on epistemic norms. In M. C. Amoretti & N. Vassallo (Eds.), Knowledge, language and interpretation: On the philosophy of Donald Davidson (pp. 123–146). Heusenstamm: Ontos Verlag.Google Scholar
  22. Geertz, C. (1973). The Interpretation of Cultures. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
  23. Gendler, T. (2008). Alief and belief. Journal of Philosophy, 105(10), 634–663.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Gertler, B. (2011). Self-knowledge. Upper Saddle River: Routledge.Google Scholar
  25. Glüer, K. (2000). Dreams and nightmares. In P. Kotatko, P. Pagin, & G. Segal (Eds.), Interpreting Davidson (pp. 53–74). Stanford: CSLI Publications.Google Scholar
  26. Godfrey-Smith, P. (2004). On folk psychology and mental representation. In H. Clapin, P. Staines, & P. Slezak (Eds.), Representation in mind: New approaches to mental representation. Amsterdam: Elsevier.Google Scholar
  27. Godfrey-Smith, P. (2005). Folk psychology as a model. Philosophers’ Imprint, 5(6), 1–16.Google Scholar
  28. Gruber, T., Deschenaux, A., Frick, A., & Clement, F. (2017). Group membership influences more social identification than social learning or overimitation in children. Child Development, Early View.Google Scholar
  29. Haslam, N. (2006). Dehumanization: an integrative review. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 10(3), 252–264.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Haslanger, S. (2012). Resisting reality: Social construction and social critique. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Hatfield, G. (2009). Perception & cognition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  32. Heyes, C. (2018). Cognitive gadgets: The cultural evolution of thinking. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Heyes, C., & Frith, C. (2014). The cultural evolution of mind reading. Nature, 344, 6190.Google Scholar
  34. Hrdy, S. (2009). Mothers and others. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  35. Humphreys, P. (2016). Emergence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Kinzler, K. D., Dupoux, E., & Spelke, E. S. (2007). The native language of social cognition. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA, 104, 12577–12580.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Lillard, A. (1998). Ethnopsychologies: Cultural variations in theories of mind. Psychological Bulletin, 123, 3–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Lomas, T. (2016). Towards a positive cross-cultural lexicography. The Journal of Positive Psychology, 11(5), 546–558.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Macfarlane, J. (2014). Assessment sensitivity: Relative truth and its applications. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Maibom, H. (2003). The mindreader and the scientist. Mind and Language, 18(3), 296–315.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Maibom, H. (2009). In defence of (model) theory theory. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 16, 360.Google Scholar
  42. Malle, B., Knobe, J., & Nelson, S. (2007). Actor-observer asymmetries in behavior explanations: New answers to an old question. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 93, 491–514.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Mallon, R. (2006). ‘Race’: normative, not metaphysical or semantic. Ethics, 116(3), 525–551.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. Mandelbaum, E. (2016). Attitude, inference, association: On the propositional structure of implicit bias. Noûs, 50(3), 629–658.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. McGeer, V. (2007). The regulative dimension of folk psychology. In D. Hutto & M. M. Ratcliffe (Eds.), Folk psychology re assessed (pp. 137–156). Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. McGeer, V. (2015). Mind-making practices: The social infrastructure of self-knowing agency and responsibility. Philosophical Explorations, 18(2), 259–281.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. Mölder, B. (2010). Mind ascribed: An elaboration and defence of interpretivism. Amsterdam: John Benjamins Publishing.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  48. Monroe, A., & Malle, B. (2017). Two paths to blame: Intentionality directs moral information processing along two distinct tracks. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 146(1), 123–133.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  49. Moran, R. (2001). Authority and estrangement: An essay on self-knowledge. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  50. Morton, A. (2003). The importance of being understood: Folk psychology as ethics. Abingdon: Routledge.Google Scholar
  51. Nisbett, R., & Wilson, T. (1977). Telling more than we can know: Verbal reports on mental processes. Psychological Review, 84(3), 231–259.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  52. O’Brien, K., Slaughter, V., & Peterson, C. C. (2011). Sibling influences on theory of mind development for children with ASD. Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry, 52, 713–719.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  53. Perez-Zapata, D., Slaughter, V., & Henry, J. (2016). Cultural effects on mindreading. Cognition, 146, 410–414.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  54. Pyers, J., Gollan, T., & Emmorey, K. (2009). Bimodal bilinguals reveal the source of tip-of-the-tongue-states. Cognition, 112, 323–329.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  55. Quilty-Dunn, J., & Mandelbaum, E. (2018). Against dispositionalism: Belief in cognitive science. Philosophical Studies, 175, 2353–2372.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  56. Quine, W. V. O. (1992). Pursuit of truth. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  57. Riddle, C. (2013). Defining disability: Metaphysical not political. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy, 16(3), 377–384.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  58. Ryle, G. (1949). The concept of mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  59. Ryle, G. (1979). On thinking. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
  60. Schroeder, T. (2003). Donald Davidson’s theory of mind is non-normative. Philosophers’ Imprint, 3(1), 1–14.Google Scholar
  61. Schwitzgebel, E. (2002). A phenomenal, dispositional account of belief. Nous, 36, 249–275.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  62. Schwitzgebel, E. (2010). Acting contrary to our professed beliefs, or the gulf between occurrent judgment and dispositional belief. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 91, 531–553.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  63. Schwitzgebel, E. (2013). A dispositional approach to attitudes: Thinking outside of the belief box. In N. Nottelmann (Ed.), New essays on belief: Constitution, content and structure (pp. 75–99). Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  64. Sellars, W. (1962). Philosophy and the scientific image of man. In R. Colodny (Ed.), Frontiers of science and philosophy. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.Google Scholar
  65. Slaughter, V., & Perez-Zapata, D. (2014). Cultural variations in the development of mindreading. Child Development Perspectives, 8(4), 237–241.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  66. Spaulding, S. (2018a). Do you see what I see? How social differences influence mindreading. Synthese, 195(9), 4009–4030.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  67. Spaulding, S. (2018b). How we understand others: Philosophy and social cognition. Abingdon: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  68. Spencer, Q. (2014). A radical solution to the race problem. Philosophy of Science, 81(5), 1025–1038.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  69. Sterelny, K. (2012). The evolved apprentice. Cambridge: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  70. Tajfel, H. (1974). Social Identity and intergroup behavior. International Social Science Council, 13(2), 65–93.Google Scholar
  71. Tanney, J. (2013). Rules, reason, and self-knowledge. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  72. Taumoepeau, M., & Ruffman, T. (2006). Mother and infant talk about mental states relates to desire language and emotion understanding. Child Development, 77, 465–481.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  73. Taumoepeau, M., & Ruffman, T. (2008). Stepping stones to others’ minds. Child Development, 79, 284–302.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  74. Taylor, P. C. (2000). Appiah’s Uncompleted Argument: W.E.B. Du Bois and the Reality of Race. Social Theory and Practice, 26(1), 103–128.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  75. Verheggen, C. (2007). Triangulating with Davidson. Philosophical Quarterly, 57(226), 96–103.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  76. Wilson, T. (2002). Strangers to ourselves: Discovering the adaptive unconscious. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  77. Wu, S., & Keysar, B. (2014). The effect of culture on perspective taking. Psychological Science, 18(7), 600–606.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  78. Zajonc, R. (2001). Mere exposure: A gateway to the subliminal. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 10(6), 224–228.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  79. Zawidzki, T. (2013). Mindshaping. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature B.V. 2018

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyThe College of WoosterWoosterUSA

Personalised recommendations