Advertisement

Vigilance and control

  • Samuel MurrayEmail author
  • Manuel Vargas
Article

Abstract

We sometimes fail unwittingly to do things that we ought to do. And we are, from time to time, culpable for these unwitting omissions. We provide an outline of a theory of responsibility for unwitting omissions. We emphasize two distinctive ideas: (1) many unwitting omissions can be understood as failures of appropriate vigilance, and; (2) the sort of self-control implicated in these failures of appropriate vigilance is valuable. We argue that the norms that govern vigilance and the value of self-control explain culpability for unwitting omissions.

Keywords

Vigilance Omission Responsibility Agency Self control 

Notes

Acknowledgements

We thank the audiences for helpful comments, especially those at the Philosophy and Science of Self-Control Conference. Special thanks to Al Mele, Adina Roskies, Katrina Sifferd, Felipe De Brigard, and Chandra Sripada for many conversations on different parts of this project. Finally, special thanks to Walter Sinnott-Armstrong and Santiago Amaya for providing written comments on multiple drafts of this paper that helped us correct many deficiencies. We also want to acknowledge the insightful criticisms of an anonymous referee at Philosophical Studies that helped us make this paper better. Research for this paper was supported by a Philosophy and Science of Self-Control grant from Florida State University through the John Templeton Foundation awarded to both Samuel Murray and Manuel Vargas. The views expressed in this paper are our own and do not reflect the opinions of the other grantees, Florida State University, or the John Templeton Foundation.

References

  1. Agule, C. K. (2016). Resisting tracing’s siren song. Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy, 10(1), 1–24.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Ahrens, M. (2016). Home fires involving cooking equipment. Quincy, MA: NFPA Fire Analysis and Research.Google Scholar
  3. Amaya, S. (2013). Slips. Noûs, 47(3), 559–576.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Amaya, S., & Doris, J. (2014). No excuses: Performance mistakes in morality. In J. Clausen & N. Levy (Eds.), Handbook of neuroethics (pp. 253–272). Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
  5. Björnsson, G. (2017). Explaining away epistemic skepticism about culpability. In D. Shoemaker (Ed.), Oxford studies in agency and responsibility (Vol. 4). New York, NY: OUP.Google Scholar
  6. Brown, J. W. (2017). Models of anterior cingulate cortex function in cognitive control. In T. Egner (Ed.), The Wiley handbook of cognitive control (pp. 259–273). London: Wiley.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Buckwalter, W., & Turri, J. (2015). Inability and obligation in moral judgment. PLoS ONE, 10(8), e0136589.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Clarke, R. (2014). Omissions: Responsibility, agency, and metaphysics. New York, NY: OUP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Cohen, J. D. (2017). Cognitive control: Core constructs and current considerations. In T. Egner (Ed.), Wiley handbook of cognitive control (pp. 3–28). New York, NY: Wiley.Google Scholar
  10. Cohen, J., Dunbar, K., & McClelland, J. L. (1990). On the control of automatic process: A parallel distributed processing account of the Stroop effect. Psychological Review, 97, 332–361.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Crocker, J., & Wolfe, C. T. (2001). Contingencies of self-worth. Psychological Review, 108(3), 593–623.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Darwall, S. (2006). The second-person standpoint: Morality, respect, and accountability. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  13. Doris, J. M. (2018). Collaborating agents: Values, sociality, and moral responsibility. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 41, e65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Einstein, G. O., & McDaniel, M. A. (2005). Prospective memory: Multiple retrieval processes. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 14(6), 286–290.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Ekstrom, L. (2000). Free will: A contemporary study. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.Google Scholar
  16. Evans, J. S. B. T., & Stanovich, K. (2013). Dual-process theories of higher cognition: Advancing the debate. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 8, 223–241.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Fischer, J. M., & Ravizza, M. (1998). Responsibility and control: A theory of moral responsibility. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Fischer, J. M., & Tognazzini, N. A. (2009). The truth about tracing. Noûs, 43(3), 531–556.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Flore, P. C., & Wicherts, J. M. (2015). Does stereotype threat influence performance of girls in stereotyped domains? Journal of School Psychology, 53(1), 25–44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Fricker, M. (2016). What’s the point of blame? A paradigm based explanation. Noûs, 50(1), 165–183.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Gadziola, M. A., & Wesson, D. W. (2016). The neural representation of goal-directed actions and outcomes in the ventral striatum’s olfactory tubercle. The Journal of Neuroscience, 36(2), 548–560.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Graham, P. A. (2014). A sketch of a theory of moral blameworthiness. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 88(2), 388–409.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Guerrero, A. A. (2007). Don’t know, don’t kill: Moral ignorance, culpability, and caution. Philosophical Studies, 136, 59–97.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Harman, E. (2011). Does moral ignorance exculpate? Ratio, 24(4), 443–468.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Hartman, R. J. (2016). Against luck-free moral responsibility. Philosophical Studies, 173(10), 2845–2865.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Heine, S. J., Lehman, D. R., Markus, H. R., & Kitayama, S. (1999). Is there a universal need for positive self-regard? Psychological Review, 106(4), 766–794.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Henne, P., Chituc, V., De Brigard, F., & Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (2016). An empirical refutation of ‘ought’ implies ‘can’. Analysis, 76(3), 283–290.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Henne, P., Pinillos, Á., & De Brigard, F. (2017). Cause by omission and norm: Not watering plants. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 95(2), 270–283.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Higgins, E. T. (1997). Beyond pleasure and pain. American Psychologist, 52, 1280.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Kool, W., & Botvinick, M. M. (2014). A labor/leisure tradeoff in cognitive control. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 143(1), 131–141.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Kool, W., Gershman, S., & Cushman, F. (2017). Cost-benefit arbitration between multiple reinforcement-learning systems. Psychological Science, 28(9), 1321–1333.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Kruger, J., & Dunning, D. (1999). Unskilled and unaware of it: How difficulties in recognizing one’s own incompetence lead to inflated self-assessments. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 77(6), 1121–1134.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Mason, E. (2015). Moral ignorance and blameworthiness. Philosophical Studies, 172, 3037–3057.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. McGeer, V. (2015). Building a better theory of responsibility. Philosophical Studies, 172(10), 2635–2649.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. McGrath, S. (2005). Causation by omission: A dilemma. Philosophical Studies, 123(1/2), 125–148.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. McKenna, M. (2012). Conversation and responsibility. New York, NY: OUP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. McKenna, M. (2013). Reasons-responsiveness, agents, and mechanisms. In D. Shoemaker (Ed.), Oxford studies in agency and responsibility (Vol. 1, pp. 151–183). OUP: New York, NY.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Mele, A. R. (2006). Practical mistakes and intentional actions. American Philosophical Quarterly, 43(3), 249–260.Google Scholar
  39. Miller, D. T., & Monin, B. (2016). Moral opportunities versus moral tests. In J. Forgas, L. Jussim, & P. van Lange (Eds.), The social psychology of morality (pp. 40–55). New York, NY: Psychology Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Murray, S. (2017). Responsibility and vigilance. Philosophical Studies, 174(2), 507–527.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Murray, S. (2018). Reference fiction, and omission. Synthese, 195(1), 235–257.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Murray, S., Murray, E. D, Stewart, G., Sinnott-Armstrong, W., & De Brigard, F. (2018). Responsibility for forgetting. Philosophical Studies.  https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-018-1053-3.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Nelkin, D. K. (2011). Making sense of freedom and responsibility. Oxford: OUP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. Posner, M. I., & Snyder, C. R. R. (1975). Attention and cognitive control. In R. L. Solso (Ed.), Information processing and cognition: The Loyola symposium. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum Associates.Google Scholar
  45. Protzko, J., & Aronson, J. (2016). Context moderates affirmation effects on the ethnic achievement gap. Social Psychological and Personality Science, 7(6), 500–507.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. Raz, J. (2011). From normativity to responsibility. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. Rosen, G. (2008). Kleinbart the oblivious and other tales of ignorance and responsibility. Journal of Philosophy, 105(10), 591–610.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  48. Roskies, A. L. (2010). Don’t panic: Self-authorship without obscure metaphysics. Philosophical Perspectives, 26, 323–342.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  49. Roskies, A. L. (2012). How does the neuroscience of decision making bear on our understanding of moral responsibility and free will. Current Opinion in Neurobiology, 22, 1022–1026.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  50. Schapiro, T. (2001). Three conceptions of action in moral theory. Noûs, 35(1), 93–117.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  51. Shabo, S. (2015). More trouble with tracing. Erkenntnis, 80, 987–1011.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  52. Shenhav, A., Botvinick, M. M., & Cohen, J. D. (2013). The expected value of control: An integrative theory of anterior cingulate cortex function. Neuron, 79, 217–240.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  53. Sher, G. (2006). Out of control. Ethics, 116(2), 285–301.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  54. Sher, G. (2009). Who knew: Responsibility without awareness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  55. Shoemaker, D. (2015). Responsibility from the margins. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  56. Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (1985). ‘Ought to have’ and ‘could have’. Analysis, 45(1), 44–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  57. Smith, A. M. (2005). Responsibility for attitudes: Activity and passivity in mental life. Ethics, 115(2), 236–271.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  58. Sripada, C. (2015). Moral responsibility, reasons, and the self. In D. Shoemaker (Ed.), Oxford studies in agency and responsibility (Vol. 3, pp. 242–264). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  59. Sripada, C. (2016). Self-expression: A deep self theory of moral responsibility. Philosophical Studies, 173, 1203–1232.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  60. Timpe, K. (2011). Tracing and the epistemic condition on moral responsibility. The Modern Schoolman, 88(1–2), 5–28.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  61. Vargas, M. (2012). Why the luck problem isn’t. Philosophical Issues, 22(1), 419–436.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  62. Vargas, M. (2013a). Building better beings. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  63. Vargas, M. (2013b). Situationism and moral responsibility: Free will in fragments. In T. Vierkant, J. Kiverstein, & A. Clark (Eds.), Decomposing the will. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  64. Watson, G. (2016). Raz on responsibility. Criminal Law and Philosophy, 10(3), 395–409.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  65. Zimmerman, M. (1986). Negligence and moral responsibility. Noûs, 20, 199–218.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature B.V. 2018

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.University of Notre DameNotre DameUSA
  2. 2.University of California, San DiegoSan DiegoUSA

Personalised recommendations