Advertisement

Philosophical Studies

, Volume 176, Issue 10, pp 2807–2831 | Cite as

Understanding as compression

  • Daniel A. WilkenfeldEmail author
Article

Abstract

What is understanding? My goal in this paper is to lay out a new approach to this question and clarify how that approach deals with certain issues. The claim is that understanding is a matter of compressing information about the understood so that it can be mentally useful. On this account, understanding amounts to having a representational kernel and the ability to use it to generate the information one needs regarding the target phenomenon. I argue that this ambitious new account can accommodate much of the data that has motivated theories of understanding in philosophy of science, and can also be generally applicable in epistemology and daily life as well.

Keywords

Explanation Understanding Philosophy of science Compression Epistemology 

Notes

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank the University of Pittsburgh, the Center for Philosophy of Science (and all its Autumn 2017 fellows), and in particular Edouard Machery, Colin Allen, Stewart Shapiro, Pablo Acuña, and Kareem Khalifa for invaluable written feedback. I also thank Tania Lombrozo for helpful conversation, and several people for help proofreading.

References

  1. Craig, E. (1990). Knowledge and the state of nature: An essay in conceptual synthesis. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  2. De Regt, H. W. (2009). The epistemic value of understanding. Philosophy of Science, 76(5), 585–597.Google Scholar
  3. De Regt, H. W., & Gijsbers, V. (2016). How false theories can yield genuine understanding. In S. R. Grimm, C. Baumberger, & S. Ammon (Eds.), Explaining understanding: New perspectives from epistemology and philosophy of science. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  4. De Regt, H. W., Leonelli, S., & Eigner, K. (2009). Scientific understanding: Philosophical perspectives. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh.Google Scholar
  5. Elgin, C. (2007). Understanding and the facts. Philosophical Studies, 132(1), 33–42.Google Scholar
  6. Forster, M., & Sober, E. (1994). How to tell when simpler, more unified, or less ad hoc theories will provide more accurate predictions. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 45(1), 1–35.Google Scholar
  7. Friedman, M. (1974). Explanation and scientific understanding. Journal of Philosophy, 71(1), 5–19.Google Scholar
  8. Grimm, S. R. (2006). Is understanding a species of knowledge? The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 57(3), 515–535.Google Scholar
  9. Grimm, S. R. (2010). The goal of explanation. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 41(4), 337–344.Google Scholar
  10. Grünwald, P. (2005). A tutorial introduction to the minimum description length principle. Retrieved from http://sites.google.com/site/mkrishnarhul/IntroMDL.pdf. Accessed 2 Oct 2017.
  11. Hempel, C. (1965). Aspects of scientific explanation and other essays in the philosophy of science. New York: The Free Press.Google Scholar
  12. Hempel, C. G., & Oppenheim, P. (1948). Studies in the logic of explanation. Philosophy of Science, 15(2), 135–175.Google Scholar
  13. Hills, A. (2016). Understanding why. Noûs, 50(4), 661–688.Google Scholar
  14. Humphreys, P. (1993). Greater unification equals greater understanding? Analysis, 53(3), 183–188.Google Scholar
  15. Kelp, C. (2015). Understanding phenomena. Synthese, 192(12), 3799–3816.Google Scholar
  16. Khalifa, K. (2017). Understanding, explanation, and scientific knowledge. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  17. Kitcher, P. (1989). Explanatory unification and the causal structure of the world. In P. Kitcher & W. Salmon (Eds.), Scientific explanation (pp. 410–505). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
  18. Kripke, S. A. (1982). Wittgenstein on rules and private language: An elementary exposition. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  19. Kvanvig, J. L. (2003). The value of knowledge and the pursuit of understanding. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  20. Lange, M. (2016). Because without cause: Non-causal explanations in science and mathematics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  21. Le Bihan, S. (2016). Enlightening falsehoods: A modal view of scientific understanding. In S. R. Grimm, C. Baumberger, & S. Ammon (Eds.), Explaining understanding: New essays in epistemology and the philosophy of science. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  22. Lewis, D. (1980). Mad pain and Martian pain. Readings in the Philosophy of Psychology, 1, 216–222.Google Scholar
  23. Machery, E. (2017). Philosophy within its proper bounds. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  24. Mizrahi, M. (2012). Idealizations and scientific understanding. Philosophical Studies, 160(2), 237–252.Google Scholar
  25. Pritchard, D. (2009). Knowledge, understanding and epistemic value. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement, 64, 19–43.Google Scholar
  26. Reisman, K., & Forber, P. (2005). Manipulation and the causes of evolution. Philosophy of Science, 72(5), 1113–1123.Google Scholar
  27. Scriven, M. (1962). Explanations, predictions, and laws. In H. Feigl, & G. Maxwell (Eds.), Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science (Vol. 3, pp. 170–229).Google Scholar
  28. Searle, J. R. (1980). Minds, brains, and programs. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 3(3), 417–424.Google Scholar
  29. Skow, B. (2014). Are there non-causal explanations? British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 65, 445–467.Google Scholar
  30. Skow, B. (2017). Levels of reasons and causal explanation. Philosophy of Science, 84(5), 905–915.Google Scholar
  31. Strevens, M. (2004). The causal and unification approaches to explanation unified—causally. Noûs, 38(1), 154–176.Google Scholar
  32. Strevens, M. (2013). No understanding without explanation. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 44(3), 510–515.Google Scholar
  33. Thagard, P. R. (1978). The best explanation: Criteria for theory choice. The Journal of Philosophy, 75(2), 76–92.Google Scholar
  34. Van Fraassen, B. C. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  35. Waskan, J. A. (2006). Models and cognition. Cambridge: A Bradford Book.Google Scholar
  36. Wilkenfeld, D. A. (2013). Understanding as representation manipulability. Synthese, 190(6), 997–1016.Google Scholar
  37. Wilkenfeld, D. A. (2014). Functional explaining: A new approach to the philosophy of explanation. Synthese, 191(14), 3367–3391.Google Scholar
  38. Wilkenfeld, D. A. (2017). MUDdy understanding. Synthese, 194(4), 1273–1293.Google Scholar
  39. Wilkenfeld, D. A., Plunkett, D., & Lombrozo, T. (2018). Folk attributions of understanding: Is there a role for epistemic luck? Episteme, 15(1), 24–49.Google Scholar
  40. Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen: A theory of causal explanation. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  41. Woodward, J. (2006). Sensitive and insensitive causation. The Philosophical Review, 115(1), 1–50.Google Scholar
  42. Woodward, J. (Ms.). Causal judgment: What can philosophy learn from experiment? What can it contribute to experiment?Google Scholar
  43. Zagzebski, L. (2001). Recovering understanding. In M. Steup (Ed.), Knowledge, truth, and duty: Essays on epistemic justification, responsibility, and virtue (pp. 235–252).Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature B.V. 2018

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of History and Philosophy of ScienceUniversity of PittsburghPittsburghUSA

Personalised recommendations