Advertisement

Philosophical Studies

, Volume 176, Issue 10, pp 2785–2805 | Cite as

Compartmentalized knowledge

  • Levi SpectreEmail author
Article
  • 326 Downloads

Abstract

This paper explores some consequences of Lewis’s (Australas J Philos 74(4):549–567, 1996) understanding of how knowledge is compartmentalized. It argues, first, that he underestimates how badly it impacts his view. When knowledge is compartmentalized, it lacks at least one of two essential features of Lewis’s account: (a) Elusiveness—familiar skeptical possibilities, when relevant, are incompatible with everyday knowledge. (b) Knowledge is a modality—when a thinker knows that p, there is no relevant possibility where p is false. Lewis proposes compartmentalized knowledge to keep treating knowledge as a modality while mitigating one of its unrealistic epistemological implications: In normal modal epistemic logic (and standard possible world semantics), a thinker always counts as knowing the strongest proposition that follows from the set of all the individual propositions that this thinker knows. Lewis’s compartmentalization proposal is that thinkers merely know the conjunctions of propositions that are known in each of, but not across, their compartments. The irony is that in avoiding overblown knowledge the view now allows for thinkers to attend to skeptical error possibilities and yet knowledge is present. The account avoids inflation of knowledge in one sense only to acquire another type of knowledge the view denies subjects can have. This problem motivates an inspection of knowledge accounts whose intra-compartment closure principles are weaker than those that are valid in normal modal-logic. The conclusion is that some formulations of closure can avoid the challenge Lewis’s view faces. Nevertheless, even these closure principles pose a barrier—perhaps an implausible barrier—for knowledge of ignorance. Even when the reasoning supporting the lack of knowledge is sound, a subject cannot always know she doesn’t know. Interestingly, this obstacle is one that knowledge of knowledge doesn’t seem to face.

Keywords

Compartmentalization Knowledge David Lewis Modal epistemic logic Normal modal logic Knowledge closure Skepticism Contextualism Subject sensitive invariantism Preface paradox Lottery paradox 

Notes

Acknowledgements

I presented several versions of this paper at Lund University; Stockholm University’s 2016 international epistemology workshop; Israel’s 2017 Philosophical Association conference; The Logic, Language, and Cognition Center at the Hebrew University; ECUP 9 at LMU Munich; University of Arizona; and University of Sheffield. I would like to thank everyone who attended. For discussions, comments, objections, and suggestions that significantly improved this paper I’m indebted to Stewart Cohen, Juan Comesaña, Julien Dutant, David Enoch, Paul Faulkner, Mikael Janvid, Moshe Halbertal, John Hawthorne, Maria Lasonen-Aarnio, Ofra Magidor, Ittay Nissan-Rozen, Erik J Olsson, Peter Pagin, Baron Reed, Daniel Rothschild, and Assaf Sharon.

References

  1. Cohen, S. (1999). Contextualism, skepticism, and the structure of reasons. Philosophical Perspectives, 13(s13), 57–89.Google Scholar
  2. Egan, A. (2008). Seeing and believing: Perception, belief formation and the divided mind. Philosophical Studies, 140(1), 47–63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Gettier, E. L. (1963). Is justified true belief knowledge? Analysis, 23(6), 121–123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Greco, D. (2015). Iteration and fragmentation. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 91(3), 656–673.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Hawthorne, J. (2002). Lewis, the lottery and the preface. Analysis, 62(3), 242–251.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Hawthorne, J. (2003). Knowledge and lotteries. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Lewis, D. (1982). Logic for equivocators. Noûs, 16(3), 431–441.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Lewis, D. (1996). Elusive knowledge. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 74(4), 549–567.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Norby, A. (2014). Against fragmentation. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy, 3(1), 30–38.Google Scholar
  10. Salow, B. (2016). Lewis on iterated knowledge. Philosophical Studies, 173(6), 1571–1590.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Sharon, A., & Spectre, L. (2013a). Epistemic closure under deductive inference: What is it and can we afford it? Synthese, 190(14), 2731–2748.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Sharon, A. & Spectre, L. (2013b). Models of internalism. MS.Google Scholar
  13. Sharon, A., & Spectre, L. (2017). Evidence and the openness of knowledge. Philosophical Studies, 174(4), 1001–1037.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Spectre, L. (2009). Knowledge closure and knowledge openness: A study of epistemic closure principles. PhD thesis, Department of Philosophy, Stockholm University.Google Scholar
  15. Stalnaker, R. (1984). Inquiry. Cambridge: MIT.Google Scholar
  16. Stanley, J. (2005). Knowledge and practical interests. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  18. Williamson, T. (2013). Gettier cases in epistemic logic. Inquiry, 56(1), 1–14.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Williamson, T. (2015). A note on gettier cases in epistemic logic. Philosophical Studies, 172(1), 129–140.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature B.V. 2018

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of History, Philosophy, and Judaic StudiesThe Open University of IsraelRa’ananaIsrael

Personalised recommendations