Advertisement

Philosophical Studies

, Volume 176, Issue 8, pp 2043–2066 | Cite as

Second best epistemology: fallibility and normativity

  • Joshua DiPaoloEmail author
Article

Abstract

The Fallibility Norm—the claim that we ought to take our fallibility into account when managing our beliefs—appears to conflict with several other compelling epistemic norms. To shed light on these apparent conflicts, I distinguish two kinds of norms: norms of perfection and norms of compensation. Roughly, norms of perfection tell us how agents ought to behave if they’re to be perfect; norms of compensation tell us how imperfect agents ought to behave in order to compensate for their imperfections. I argue that the Fallibility Norm is a norm of compensation, and that thinking of it like this helps us make progress in debates surrounding disagreement, higher-order evidence, and coherence.

Keywords

Fallibility Normativity Imperfection Disagreement Coherence 

Notes

Acknowledgements

I owe thanks to many people for helpful comments, discussion, and encouragement concerning this paper. Thanks are especially due to Hilary Kornblith, Chris Meacham, and Katia Vavova. Thanks also to Jeff Behrends, Asia Ferrin, Bruce Glymour, Scott Hill, Daniel Immerman, Graham Leach-Krouse, Han Li, Jon Mahoney, Luis Oliveira, Gina Schouten, Robert Simpson, Mike Titelbaum, and several anonymous referees. Finally, I’m grateful to Doug Portmore for initiating my reflection on the relationship between ideal and non-ideal theory. As an undergraduate in Doug’s Ethical Theory class in the early 2000s, I made a bad inference about the normative relationship between the ideal world and our non-ideal world. I’ve learned a lot from thinking about the brief discussion I had with Doug as a result of making this inference.

References

  1. Anderson, E. (2010). The imperative of integration. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Aqvist, L. (1967). Good samaritans, contrary-to-duty imperatives, and epistemic obligations. Nous, 1(4), 361–379.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Casteneda, H. N. (1981). The paradoxes of deontic logic: The simplest solution to all of them in one fell swoop. In R. Hilpinen (Ed.), New studies in deontic logic: Norms, actions, and the foundations of ethics (pp. 378–385). Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar
  4. Chisholm, R. (1963). Contrary-to-duty imperatives and deontic logic. Analysis, 24, 33–36.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Christensen, D. (2007). Does Murphy’s law apply in epistemology? Oxford Studies in Epistemology, 2, 3–31.Google Scholar
  6. Christensen, D. (2010). Higher-order evidence. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 81, 185–215.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Christensen, D. (2011). Disagreement, question-begging, and epistemic self-criticism. Philosopher’s Imprint, 11, 1–22.Google Scholar
  8. Christensen, D. (2013). Epistemic modesty defended. In D. Christensen & J. Lackey (Eds.), the epistemology of disagreement: New essays (pp. 77–97). New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. DiPaolo, J. (2017). Evidence and fallibility. Episteme.  https://doi.org/10.1017/epi.2017.17. (first view).Google Scholar
  10. Egan, A. (2008). Seeing and believing: Perception, belief formation, and the divided mind. Philosophical Studies, 140, 47–63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Egan, A., & Elga, A. (2005). I can’t believe I’m stupid. Philosophical Perspectives, 19, 77–93.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Elga, A. (2010). How to disagree about how to disagree. In R. Feldman & T. Warfield (Eds.), Disagreement (pp. 175–186). New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Elga, A. (2013). The puzzle of the unmarked clock and the new rational reflection principle. Philosophical Studies, 164(1), 127–139.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Feldman, F. (1990). A simpler solution to the paradoxes of deontic logic. Philosophical Perspectives, 4, 309–341.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Foley, R. (1993). Working without a net. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  16. Greco, D. (2014). A puzzle about epistemic akrasia. Philosophical Studies, 167, 201–219.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Horowitz, S. (2014). Epistemic akrasia. Nous, 48, 718–744.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Kratzer, A. (1991). Modality. In D. W. Arnim von Stechow (Ed.), Semantics: An international handbook of contemporary research (pp. 639–650). Berlin: W. de Gruyter.Google Scholar
  19. Lasonen-Aarnio, M. (2014). Higher-order evidence and the limits of defeat. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 88, 314–345.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Lewis, D. (1971). Immodest inductive methods. Philosophy of Science, 38, 54–63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Lewis, D. (1986a). A subjectivist’s guide to objective chance. Philosophical papers (Vol. II, pp. 83–132). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  22. Lewis, D. (1986b). Probabilities of conditionals and conditional probabilities II. The Philosophical Review, 95, 581–589.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Lewis, D. (1999). Why conditionalize? Papers in metaphysics and epistemology (pp. 403–407). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Lipsey, R., & Lancaster, K. (1956). The general theory of the second best. The Review of Economic Studies, 24, 1–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Nozick, R. (1974). Anarchy, state, and Utopia. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
  26. Rawls, J. (1999a). A theory of justice: Revised editoin. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  27. Rawls, J. (1999b). The law of peoples. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  28. Ross, W. D. (1930). The right and the good. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  29. Schechter, J. (2013). Rational self-doubt and the failure of closure. Philosophical Studies, 163, 429–452.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Sliwa, P., & Horowitz, S. (2015). Respecting all the evidence. Philosophical Studies, 172, 2835–2858.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Srinivasan, A. (2015). Are we luminous? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 90(2), 294–319.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Titelbaum, M. (2015). Rationality’s fixed point (or: in defense of right reason). Oxford studies in epistemology (Vol. 5). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  33. Van Fraassen, B. C. (1972). The logic of conditional obligation. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 1, 417–438.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Van Wietmarschen, H. (2013). Peer disagreement, evidence, and well-groundedness. Philosophical Review, 122, 395–425.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Vavova, K. (2015). Moral disagreement and moral skepticism. Philosophical Perspectives, 28, 302–333.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Weatherson, B. (2013). Disagreements, philosophical and otherwise. In D. Christensen & J. Lackey (Eds.), The epistemology of disagreement: New essays (pp. 54–73). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  38. Worsnip, A. (2015). The conflict of evidence and coherence. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research.  https://doi.org/10.1111/phpr.12246.Google Scholar
  39. Zynda, L. (1996). Coherence as an ideal of rationality. Synthese, 109, 175–216.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V., part of Springer Nature 2018

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyKansas State UniversityManhattanUSA

Personalised recommendations