Advertisement

Philosophical Studies

, Volume 175, Issue 10, pp 2399–2417 | Cite as

Supererogation, optionality and cost

  • Claire BennEmail author
Article

Abstract

A familiar part of debates about supererogatory actions concerns the role that cost should play. Two camps have emerged: one claiming that extreme cost is a necessary condition for when (and why) an action is supererogatory, while the other denies that it should be part of our definition of supererogation. In this paper, I propose an alternative position. I argue that it is comparative cost that is central to the supererogatory and that it is needed to explain a feature that all accounts agree is central to the very notion of supererogation: optionality. Perhaps because of this agreement on its importance, few attempts have been made to clarify and explain the notion of optionality. I argue that giving an account of the optionality of supererogatory requires drawing a line between doing the bare minimum permissible and going beyond the bare minimum and that this line ought to be drawn based on comparative cost of alternative permissible acts. Having outlined my account and motivated it, I discuss and reject two concerns that might be raised: firstly, that it is extreme cost, not comparative cost, that matters and, secondly, that in fact no cost is needed for an act to be supererogatory.

Keywords

Cost Duty Optionality Permissibility Sacrifice Supererogation 

Notes

Acknowledgements

Many thanks to Rae Langton, Hallvard Lillehammer, Douglas Portmore, Georgie Statham, Tristan Hore, Christine Fears, Shyane Siriwardena, Christina Cameron, Silvia Jonas, Sharon Berry, Olla Solomyak and an anonymous reviewer; also audiences at the University of Cambridge Moral Sciences Club, the Hebrew University Faculty of Philosophy Colloquium, the Centre for Ethical and Political Philosophy at the Hebrew University of Jerusalem, The Polonsky Academy for Advanced Study, and the Centre for Applied Philosophy and Ethics (CAPE), Kyoto University Japan.

References

  1. Allen, R. T. (1981). Supererogation revised. Sophia, 20 (2), 5–11. http://www.springerlink.com/index/D65013628100083L.pdf.
  2. Archer, A. (2013). Supererogation and intentions of the agent. Philosophia (United States), 41(2), 447–462. doi: 10.1007/s11406-013-9422-9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Archer, A. (2015). Are acts of supererogation always praiseworthy? Theoria. doi: 10.1111/theo.12085.Google Scholar
  4. Archer, A. (2016). Supererogation, sacrifice and the limits of duty. Southern Journal of Philosophy, 54(3), 333–354.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Attfield, R. (1979). Supererogation and double standards. Mind, 88 (352), 481–99. http://mind.oxfordjournals.org/content/LXXXVIII/1/481.full.pdf.
  6. Baron, M. (1987). Kantian ethics and supererogation. The Journal of Philosophy, 84 (5), 237–62. http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.2307/2026752.
  7. Benn, C. (2016). Over-demandingness objections and supererogation. In Marcel van Ackeren and Michael Kühler (Eds.) The limits of moral obligation, (pp. 68–83). Routledge.Google Scholar
  8. Benn, C. (2017). Supererogatory spandrels. Etica & Politica/Ethics and Politics, 19(1), 269–290.Google Scholar
  9. Calhoun, C. (2004) Common decency. In Calhoun, C. (Eds.) Setting the moral compass, (pp. 128–42). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  10. Chisholm, R. M. (1964). The ethics of requirement. American Philosophical Quarterly, 1(2), 147–153.Google Scholar
  11. Chisholm, R. M., & Sosa, E. (1966). Intrinsic preferability and the problem of supererogation. Synthese 16, 321–31. http://www.springerlink.com/index/n315h744735h5174.pdf.
  12. Cohen, G. A. (1989). On the currency of egalitarian justice. Ethics, 99(4), 906–944. doi: 10.1086/293126.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Darwin, C. (1871). The descent of man, and selection in relation to sex. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Feinberg, J. (1961). Supererogation and rules. Ethics 71 (4), 276–88. http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.2307/2379643.
  15. Heyd, D. (1982). Supererogation: Its status in ethical theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  16. Horgan, T., & Timmons, Mark. (2010). Untying a knot from the inside out: Reflections on the ‘paradox’ of supererogation. Social Philosophy and Policy Foundation, 27(2), 29–63. doi: 10.1017/S026505250999015X.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Jackson, M. W. (1986). The Nature of Supererogation. The Journal of Value Inquiry 20, 289–96. http://link.springer.com/article/10.1007/BF00146118.
  18. Jacobs, R. A. (1987). Obligation, supererogation and self-sacrifice. Philosophy, 62 (239), 96–101. http://www.jstor.org/stable/3751025.
  19. Kawall, Jason. (2003). Self-regarding supererogatory actions. Journal of Social Philosophy, 34(3), 487–498. doi: 10.1111/1467-9833.00196.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. McGoldrick, P. M. (1984). Saints and heroes: A plea for the supererogatory. Philosophy 59 (230), 523–28. http://www.jstor.org/stable/3750369.
  21. McNamara, P. (1996). Making room for going beyond the call. Mind 105 (419), 415–50. http://mind.oxfordjournals.org/content/105/419/415.short.
  22. Mellema, G. (1991a). Beyond the call of duty. Buffalo: State University of New York.Google Scholar
  23. Mellema, G. (1991b). Supererogation and the fulfillment of duty. The Journal of Value Inquiry, 25, 167–75. http://www.springerlink.com/index/N475156P93R4V4N2.pdf.
  24. Montague, P. (1989). Acts, agents, and supererogation. American Philosophical Quarterly, 26 (2), 101–11. http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.2307/20014275.
  25. Murphy, L. (1993). The demands of beneficence. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 22 (4), 267–92. http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.2307/2265468.
  26. Murphy, L. (2000). Moral demands in nonideal theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  27. Overvold, M. C. (1980). Self-interest and the concept of self-sacrifice. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 10 (1), 105–18. http://www.jstor.org/stable/40231134.
  28. Portmore, D. W. (2003). Position-relative consequentialism, agent-centered options, and supererogation. Ethics, 113 (2), 303–32. http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.1086/342859.
  29. Pybus, E. M. (1982). Saints and heroes. Philosophy, 57(220), 193–199.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Rawls, J. (1999). A theory of justice (Rev. Ed.). Cambridge: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  31. Raz, J. (1975). Permissions and Supererogation. American Philosophical Quarterly, 12 (2), 161–68. http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.2307/20009570.
  32. Stanlick, N. A. (1999). The nature and value of supererogatory actions. Journal of Social Philosophy, 30(1), 209–222. doi: 10.1111/0047-2786.t01-1-00013.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Stocker, M. (1967). Acts, perfect duties, and imperfect duties. The Review of Metaphysics, 20 (3), 507–17. http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.2307/20124315.
  34. Straumanis, J. (1984). Duties to oneself: An ethical basis for self-liberation? Journal of Social Philosophy, 15, 1–13.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2017

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Polonsky Academy FellowVan Leer Jerusalem InstituteJerusalemIsrael

Personalised recommendations