Advertisement

Philosophical Studies

, Volume 175, Issue 7, pp 1703–1727 | Cite as

Knowledge-how is the norm of intention

  • Joshua Habgood-Coote
Article

Abstract

It is a widely shared intuition that there is a close connection between knowledge-how and intentional action. In this paper, I explore one aspect of this connection: the normative connection between intending to do something and knowing how to do it. I argue for a norm connecting knowledge-how and intending in a way that parallels the knowledge norms of assertion, belief, and practical reasoning, which I call the knowledge-how norm of Intention. I argue that this norm can appeal to support from arguments which parallel those for other epistemic norms, that it can deal with a number of prima facie problem cases, and that alternative conditions in a norm on intention are implausible.

Keywords

Knowledge-how Epistemic norms Intention Partial plans Bratman 

Notes

Acknowledgements

Thanks to: Dylan Bianchi, Jessica Brown, Niel Conradie, Nilanjan Das, Philip Ebert, Rachel Fraser, Abby Jacques, Brendan de Kenessey, Katherine Hawley, Matthew McGrath, Sarah Paul, Carlotta Pavese, Ginger Schultheis, Kieran Setiya, Justin Snedegar, Eric Swanson, Caroline Touborg, Michael Wheeler, Quinn White, Marissa Wallin, an anonymous reviewer for this journal, and audiences in St Andrews, MIT, and Valladolid.

Funding

Funding was provided by Arts and Humanities Research Council (GB).

References

  1. Anscombe, G. E. M. (1957). Intention. Harvard: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  2. Bach, K. (2008). Applying pragmatics to epistemology. Philosophical Issues, 18(1), 68–88.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Bach, K., & Harnish, R. M. (1979). Linguistic communication and speech acts. Cambridge: MIT press.Google Scholar
  4. Bengson, J., & Moffett, M. (2011). Non-propositional intellectualism. In J. Bengson & M. Moffett (Eds.), Knowing how (pp. 161–195). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  5. Bhatt, R. (2006). Covert modality in non-finite contexts. Berlin: Molton De Gruyter.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Boyd, K. (2015). Assertion, practical reasoning, and epistemic separabilism. Philosophical Studies, 172(7), 1907–1927.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Bratman, M. (1987). Intentions, plans, and practical reason. Harvard: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  8. Bratman, M. (2009a). Intention, belief, and instrumental rationality. In S. David & S. Wall (Eds.), Reasons for action (pp. 13–36). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Bratman, M. (2009b). Intention, Belief, Practical, Theoretical. In S. Robertson (Ed.), Spheres of reason: New essays in the philosophy of normativity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  10. Braun, D. (2006). Now you know who Hong Oak yun is. Philosophical Issues, 16(1), 24–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Braun, D. (2011). Knowing how and knowing answers. In J. Bengson & M. A. Moffett (Eds.), Knowing how: Essays on knowledge, mind, and action1 (pp. 244–260). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  12. Broome, J. (1999). Normative requirements. Ratio, 12(4), 398–419.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Broome, J. (2005). Does rationality give us reasons? Philosophical Issues, 15(1), 321–337.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Broome, J. (2013). Rationality through reasoning. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Brown, J. (2008). The knowledge norm for assertion. Philosophical Issues, 12, 89–103.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Buckwalter, W., & Turri, J. (2014). Telling, showing and knowing: A unified theory of pedagogical norms. Analysis, 74(1), 16–20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Cath, Y. (2015). Revisionary intellectualism and Gettier. Philosophical Studies, 172(1), 7–27.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Craig, E. (1990). Knowledge and the state of nature. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  19. Dancy, J. (2004). Ethics without principles. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. DeRose, K. (2002). Assertion, knowledge, and context. Philosophical Review, 111(2), 167–203.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Douven, I. (2006). Assertion, knowledge, and rational credibility. Philosophical Review, 115(4), 449–485.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Ericsson, K. (2006). The influence of experience and deliberate practice on the development of superior expert practice. In K. Ericsson et al. (Eds.), The Cambridge handbook of expertise and expert performance (pp. 683–704). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Fantl, J., & McGrath, M. (2009). Knowledge in an uncertain world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Ferrero, L., MS Intending, Acting, and Doing Intending, Acting, and Doing.Google Scholar
  25. Ford, A., Hornsby, J., & Stoutland, F. (2011). Essays on Anscombe’s intention. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Gerken, M. (2015). The roles of knowledge ascriptions in epistemic assessment. European Journal of Philosophy, 23(1), 141–161.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Gibbons, J. (2001). Knowledge in action. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 62(3), 579–600.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Grice, H. P. (1972). Intention and uncertainty. Proceedings of the British Academy, 57, 267–279.Google Scholar
  29. Habgood-Coote, J. (2017). Knowing-how. Showing, and Epistemic Norms, Synthese, online first. doi: 10.1007/s11229-017-1389-9.Google Scholar
  30. Harman, G. (1976). Practical reasoning. Review of Metaphysics, 29, 431–463.Google Scholar
  31. Hawley, K. (2003). Success and knowledge-how. American Philosophical Quarterly, 40(1), 19–31.Google Scholar
  32. Hawley, K. (2011). Knowing How and Epistemic Injustice. In J. Bengson & M. A. Moffett (Eds.), Knowing how: Essays on knowledge, mind, and action (pp. 283–299). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  33. Hawthorne, J. (2003). Knowledge and lotteries. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Hawthorne, J., & Stanley, J. (2008). Knowledge and action. Journal of Philosophy, 105(10), 571–590.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Hedden, B. (2012). Options and the subjective ought. Philosophical Studies, 158(2), 343–360.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Hedden, B. (2015). Options and diachronic tragedy. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 90(2), 423–451.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Holton, R. (2008). Partial belief. Partial Intention. Mind, 117(465), 27–58.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Hornsby, J. (2005). Semantic knowledge and practical knowledge. Aristotelian Society Supplementary, 79(Section I), 107–145.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Hornsby, J. (2016). Intending, knowing how, infinitives. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 46(1), 1–17.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Kratzer, A. (1977). What “must” and “can” must and can mean. Linguistics and Philosophy, 1(3), 337–355.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Kruger, J., & Dunning, D. (1999). Unskilled and unaware of it: How difficulties in recognizing one’s own incompetence lead to inflated self-assessments. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 77(6), 1121–1134.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Kumar, V. (2011). In support of anti-intellectualism. Philosophical Studies, 152(1), 135–154.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Kvanvig, J. (2011). Norms of assertion. In J. Brown & H. Cappelen (Eds.), Assertion: New philosophical essays. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  44. Lackey, J. (2008). Learning from words: Testimony as a source of knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. Langton, R. (2004). Intention as faith. In H. Steward & J. Hyman (Eds.), Royal institute of philosophy supplement. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  46. Lasonen-Aarnio, M. (2014). Higher-order evidence and the limits of defeat. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 88(2), 314–345.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. Lewis, D. (1996). Elusive knowledge. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 74(4), 549–567.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  48. Littlejohn, C. (2009). The externalist’s demon. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 39(3), 399–434.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  49. Marušić, B. (2012). Belief and difficult action. Philosophers’ Imprint, 12(18), 1–30.Google Scholar
  50. Marušić, B. (2015). Evidence and agency: Norms of belief for promising and resolving. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  51. McGlynn, A. (2014). Knowledge first?. Palgrave Macmillian.Google Scholar
  52. Montero, B. (2016). Thought in action: Expertise and the conscious mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  53. Moore, A. W. (1997). Points of view. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  54. Moran, R. (2004). Anscombe on “practical knowledge”. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement, 55, 43–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  55. Moran, R., & Stone, M. J. (2011). Anscombe on expression of intention : An exegesis. In A. Ford, J. Hornsby, & F. Stoutland (Eds.), Essays on Anscombe’s intention (pp. 33–75). Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  56. Parent, T. (2014). Knowing-wh and embedded questions. Philosophy compass, 9(2), 81–95. http://doi.wiley.com/10.1111/phc3.12104.
  57. Paul, S. (2009a). How we know what we’re doing. Philosophers’ Imprint, 9(11), 1–24.Google Scholar
  58. Paul, S. (2009b). Intention, belief, and wishful thinking: Setiya on “practical knowledge”. Ethics, 119(3), 546–557.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  59. Pavese, C. (2017). Know how and gradability. Philosophical Review, 123(3).Google Scholar
  60. Pelling, C. (2013). Assertion and safety. Synthese, 190(17), 3777-3796.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  61. Portner, P. (2007). Imperatives and modals. Natural Language Semantics, 15(4), 351–383.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  62. Pritchard, D. (2005). Epistemic luck. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  63. Ryle, G. (2009). The concept of mind (60th Anniversary edition). London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  64. Schroeder, M. (2009). Means-end coherence, stringency, and subjective reasons. Philosophical Studies, 143(2), 223–248.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  65. Searle, J. (1979). Indirect speech acts. Expression and meaning (pp. 30–57). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  66. Setiya, K. (2007). Cognitivism about instrumental reason. Ethics, 117(4), 649–673.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  67. Setiya, K. (2008). Practical knowledge. Ethics, 118(3), 388–409.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  68. Setiya, K. (2009). Practical knowledge revisited. Ethics, 120(1), 128–137.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  69. Setiya, K. (2012). Knowing how. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (Hardback), 112(3), 285–307.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  70. Setiya, K. (2016). Practical knowledge: Selected essays. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  71. Slote, M. (1979). Assertion and belief. In J. Dancy (Ed.), Papers on language and logic (pp. 177–190). Keele: Keele University Library.Google Scholar
  72. Snedegar, J., MS ‘Deliberation, Reasons, and Alternatives.Google Scholar
  73. Stanley, J. (2011). Know how. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  74. Stanley, J., & Williamson, T. (2001). Knowing how. Journal of Philosophy, 98(8), 411–444.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  75. Sutton, J. (2007). Without justification. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  76. Thompson, M. (2008). Life and action: Elementary structures of practice and practical thought. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  77. Turri, J. (2011). The express knowledge account of assertion. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 89(1), 37–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  78. Unger, P. K. (1975). Ignorance: A case for scepticism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  79. Velleman, D. (1989). Practical reflection. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  80. Weatherson, B. (2012). Knowledge, bets, and interests. In Jessica Brown & Mikkel Gerken (Eds.), Knowledge ascriptions (pp. 75–103). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  81. Weiner, M. (2005). Must we know what we say? The Philosophical Review, 114(2), 227–251.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  82. Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  83. Williamson, T. (2005). Contextualism, subject-sensitive inv ariantism and knowledge of knowledge. 55.Google Scholar
  84. Williamson, T. (forthcoming) Justifications, excuses, and skeptical scenarios. In F. Dorsch & J. Dutant (Eds.), The new evil demon: New essays on knowledge, rationality and justification. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2017

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyUniversity of St AndrewsFifeUK

Personalised recommendations