Advertisement

Philosophical Studies

, Volume 175, Issue 2, pp 411–428 | Cite as

Ability, modality, and genericity

  • John MaierEmail author
Article

Abstract

Accounts of ability in the philosophical literature have tended to be modal ones: claims about an agent’s abilities are understood in terms of what she does in certain non-actual scenarios. In contrast, a prominent account of ability ascriptions in the recent semantics literature appeals to genericity: claims about an agent’s abilities are understood in terms of what she generally manages to do. The latter account resolves some long-standing problems for modal accounts, but encounters problems of its own. I propose a hybrid view, on which ability involves both a modal and a generic element.

Keywords

Abilities Genericity Modal logic 

References

  1. Austin, J. L. (1956). Ifs and cans. In Philosophical papers (1961). Oxford: Clarendon PressGoogle Scholar
  2. Belnap, N., & Perloff, M. (1988). Seeing to it that: A canonical form for agentives. Theoria, 54, 175–199.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Bhatt, R. (1999). Covert modality in non-finite contexts. Dissertation, University of Pennsylvania.Google Scholar
  4. Brown, M. (1988). On the logic of ability. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 17, 1–26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Carlson, G., & Pelletier, F. (Eds.). (1995). The generic book. Chicago: University of Chicago P.Google Scholar
  6. Cross, C. (1986). ‘Can’ and the logic of ability. Philosophical Studies, 50, 53–64.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Davidson, D. (1967). The logical form of action sentences. In N. Rescher (Ed.), The logic of decision and action. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.Google Scholar
  8. Fara, M. (2010). Knowability and the capacity to know. Synthese, 2010, 53–73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Fine, K. (1994). Essence and modality. Philosophical Perspectives, 8, 1–16.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Horty, J. (2001). Agency and deontic logic. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Horty, J., & Belnap, N. (1995). The deliberative stit: A study of action, omission, ability, and obligation. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 24, 583–644.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Horty, J., & Pacuit, E. (Unpublished ms). Action Types in Stit Semantics.Google Scholar
  13. Kenny, A. (1975). Will, freedom, and power. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  14. Kratzer, A. (1981). The notional category of modality. In H. J. Eikmeyer & H. Rieser (Eds.), Words, worlds, and contexts. Berlin: de Gruyter.Google Scholar
  15. Kripke, S. (1963). Semantical considerations on modal logic. Acta Philosophica Fennica, 16, 83–94.Google Scholar
  16. Maier, J. (2015). The agentive modalities. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 90, 113–134.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Mandelkern, M., Schultheis, G., & Boylan, D. (ms). Agentive modals. The Philosophical Review. (Forthcoming).Google Scholar
  18. Portner, P. (2009). Modality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  19. Spencer, J. (ms). Able to do the impossible. Mind. (Forthcoming).Google Scholar
  20. Stalnaker, R. (1968). A theory of conditionals. In N. Rescher (Ed.), Studies in logical theory. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  21. Thomason, R. (Unpublished ms). Defeasibly successful action.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2017

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyPeking UniversityBeijingChina

Personalised recommendations