Advertisement

Philosophical Studies

, Volume 175, Issue 2, pp 277–300 | Cite as

Downward mobility and Rawlsian justice

  • Govind PersadEmail author
Article

Abstract

Technological and societal changes have made downward social and economic mobility a pressing issue in real-world politics. This article argues that a Rawlsian society would not provide any special protection against downward mobility, and would act rightly in declining to provide such protection. Special treatment for the downwardly mobile can be grounded neither in Rawls’s core principles—the basic liberties, fair equality of opportunity, and the difference principle—nor in other aspects of Rawls’s theory (the concept of legitimate expectations, the idea of a life plan, the distinction between allocative and distributive justice, or the distinction between ideal and nonideal theory). Instead, a Rawlsian society is willing to sacrifice particular individuals’ ambitions and plans for the achievement of justice, and offers those who lose out from justified change no special solicitude over and above the general solicitude extended to all. Rather than guaranteeing the maintenance of any particular individual or group’s economic position, it provides all of its members—the upwardly mobile, the downwardly mobile, and the immobile—a form of security that is at once more generous and more limited: that they will receive the liberties, opportunities, and resources promised by the principles of justice.

Keywords

Social mobility Economic mobility Legitimate expectations Trade Automation Social change John Rawls 

Notes

Acknowledgements

I am grateful to Debra Satz, Joshua Cohen, Eamonn Callan, Mark Kelman, Jorah Dannenberg, Collin Anthony, RJ Leland, Samuel Freeman, Nien-hê Hsieh, Shim Reza, and an anonymous referee at Philosophical Studies for written comments and detailed discussion. Thanks also to audiences at the 2012 National Endowment for the Humanities Summer Seminar on Liberty, Equality, and Justice; the 2012 Harvard Graduate Conference in Political Theory; and the 2014 Ethics and Politics, Ancient and Modern workshop at Stanford University.

References

  1. Arvan, M. (2014). First steps toward a non-ideal theory of justice. Ethics and Global Politics, 7, 95–117.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Bertram, C. (2006). Cosmopolitanism and Inequality. Res Publica, 12, 327–336.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Bertram, C. (2012) “The Problem of Rawlsian Transition,” posting to Crooked Timber, August 7, 2012. http://crookedtimber.org/2012/08/07/the-problem-of-rawlsian-transition/.
  4. Brown, A. (2012). Rawls, Buchanan, and the legal doctrine of legitimate expectations. Social Theory and Practice, 38, 617–644.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Buchanan, A. (1975). Distributive justice and legitimate expectations. Philosophical Studies, 28, 419–425.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Chambers, C. (2009). Each outcome is another opportunity: Problems with the moment of equal opportunity. Politics, Philosophy, and Economics, 8, 374–400.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Cohen, J. (1993). Pluralism and proceduralism. Chicago-Kent Law Review, 69, 589–618.Google Scholar
  8. Cohen, J. (2001). Taking people as they are? Philosophy & Public Affairs, 30(4), 363–386.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Cohen, J. (with Seth Resler) (2011). “Occupation as fairness: What John Rawls would make of the occupy movement,” Boston Review (Nov. 17, 2011), http://bostonreview.net/joshua-cohen-seth-resler-john-rawls-occupy-wall-street.
  10. Dworkin, R. (2002). Sovereign virtue. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  11. Feinberg, J. (1989). “Rawls and Intuitionism”, in Norman Daniels, Reading Rawls. Stanford: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
  12. Føllesdal, A. (2001). Union citizenship: Unpacking the beast of burden. Law and Philosophy, 20, 313–343.Google Scholar
  13. Francis, L. P. (2002). Age rationing under conditions of injustice. In R. Rhodes et al. (Eds.), Medicine and social justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  14. Freeman, S. (2011). Capitalism in the classical and high liberal traditions. Social Philosophy and Policy, 28, 19–55.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Hart, H. L. A. (1973). Rawls on liberty and its priority. University of Chicago Law Review, 40, 534–555.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Hayek, F. A. (1976). Law, legislation, and liberty, Vol. 2: The mirage of social justice. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  17. Hsieh, N. (2000). Moral desert, fairness and legitimate expectations in the market. Journal of Political Philosophy, 8, 91–114.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. James, A. (2012). Fairness in practice. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Lister, A. (2013). The ‘Mirage’ of Social Justice: Hayek Against (and for) Rawls. Critical Review, 25, 409–444.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Marmor, A. (2004). The rule of law and its limits. Law and Philosophy, 23, 1–42.Google Scholar
  21. Mazie, S. (2011) “Rawls on Wall Street,” The New York Times (October 21, 2011). http://opinionator.blogs.nytimes.com/2011/10/21/rawls-on-wall-street/.
  22. Meyer, L. H., & Sanklecha, P. (2011). Individual expectations and climate justice. Analyse & Kritik, 2, 449–471.Google Scholar
  23. Nozick, R. (1974). Anarchy, state, and utopia. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
  24. Paul, E. F. (1981). The just takings issue. Environmental Ethics, 3, 309–328.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Rawls, J. (1999). A theory of justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  26. Rawls, J. (2001). Collected papers. In S. Freeman (Ed.). Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Google Scholar
  27. Swanton, C. (1981). Is the difference principle a principle of justice? Mind, 90, 415–421.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Taylor, R. S. (2004). Self-realization and the priority of fair equality of opportunity. Journal of Moral Philosophy, 1(3), 333–347.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Waldron, J. (2002). The rule of law in contemporary liberal theory. In G. W. Smith (Ed.), Liberalism: Rights, property and markets. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
  30. Waldron, J. (2005). Nozick and Locke: Filling the space of rights. Social Philosophy and Policy, 22, 81–110.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Waldron, J. (2012). The rule of law and the measure of property. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2017

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Berman Institute of BioethicsJohns Hopkins UniversityBaltimoreUSA

Personalised recommendations